U.S. flag

An official website of the United States government

The .gov means it’s official. Federal government websites often end in .gov or .mil. Before sharing sensitive information, make sure you’re on a federal government site.

The site is secure. The https:// ensures that you are connecting to the official website and that any information you provide is encrypted and transmitted securely.

  • Publications
  • Account settings

Preview improvements coming to the PMC website in October 2024. Learn More or Try it out now .

  • Advanced Search
  • Journal List
  • Arch Dis Child Fetal Neonatal Ed
  • v.91(1); 2006 Jan

Logo of archdischfn

Aristotle (384–322 bc ): philosopher and scientist of ancient Greece

Aristotle's studies encompassed the entire world of living things. Many of his descriptions and classifications remain sound today. Although not a physician, he exerted a profound influence on medicine for the next 2000 years.

Aristotle was one of the greatest philosophers and scientists the world has ever seen. He was born in 384 bc at Stagirus, a Greek seaport on the coast of Thrace. His father, Nichomachus, court physician to King Amyntus II of Macedon, died while he was still a boy, and his guardian, Proxenus, sent him to complete his education at the age of 17 in Plato's Academy in Athens. He remained there for the next 20 years, first as a pupil and later as a teacher. Plato and Aristotle recognised each other's outstanding qualities, but they had frequent arguments and disagreements. Whereas Plato believed that reality existed in ideas, knowable only through reflection and inspiration, Aristotle saw ultimate reality in physical objects, knowable through the experience of the five senses. He believed that every problem had an objective solution. His was a scientific approach. Of his master he wrote: “Plato is my friend but truth is much more”.

When Plato died in 347 bc , Aristotle, aged 37, was not appointed to succeed him. Perhaps his differences with Plato were too great. He then left Athens to spend the next five years in Asia Minor at the court of Hermeas, ruler of Atarneus in Mysia, whose niece and adopted daughter, Pythias, he married. In later life he married a second time a woman named Perpyllis, who bore him a son, named Nichomachus after his father. In Asia Minor and later in Mytilene (Lesbos), Aristotle pursued his studies in biology and natural history until, in 342 bc , he was recalled to Macedon by Phillip II (King Amyntas' son) to act as tutor to his 14 year old son Alexander. Seven years later, in 336 bc , Phillip was assassinated, and the following year Alexander, now king, set out on his conquest of the Persian Empire. At this time, Aristotle at the age of 49 returned to Athens to found his own school of philosophy, The Lyceum. It was nicknamed the “peripatetic school” because of Aristotle's practice of lecturing his students while walking around the school's garden (fig 1 ​ 1). ). Besides teaching, Aristotle amassed a large collection of manuscripts, which later found their way to the library in Alexandria. He also cultivated a botanical garden. His disciple and successor, Theophrastus of Eresos (370–287 bc ) later based his De historia plantarum on this garden, listing 500 plants.

An external file that holds a picture, illustration, etc.
Object name is fn74534.f1.jpg

Figure 1  Aristotle (384–322 bc ).

When news of Alexander's death in Babylon reached Athens in 323 bc , Aristotle, fearing an anti‐Macedonian reaction, prudently withdrew from Athens to Chalcis in Euboea, his mother's home town. There the following year, 322 bc , he died of a stomach illness. He was 62. 1 , 2 , 3 , 4 , 5

Aristotle's lectures were collected into nearly 150 volumes and represented an encyclopaedia of the knowledge of his day, much of it indeed his own contribution. Unfortunately, less than a third of his writings have survived. Although Aristotle's most important work was on biology, he also dealt with logic, metaphysics, psychology, meteorology, politics, literary criticism, poetry, drama, and ethics. Although he was not a doctor, his contributions to medicine were immense. He was the first to treat systematically the fields of botany, zoology, anatomy, embryology, teratology, and physiology. Aristotle was assisted by his great faith in nature, writing: “In all things of nature there is something of the marvellous”, “Nature does nothing uselessly”, and “If one way be better than another, that you may be sure is nature's way.”

Starting as he did virtually from scratch, it is hardly surprising that some of Aristotle's explanations as to how the human body functioned were incorrect. For instance, like Hippocrates, he subscribed to the humeral theory of disease holding that there were four primary fundamental “qualities” in life: hot, cold, wet, and dry. These met in binary combination to constitute the four “elements”: earth, air, fire, and water, represented respectively by black bile, yellow bile, blood, and phlegm. The body was thought to be composed of these “humours”, which were responsible for the temperaments: melancholy, choleric, sanguine, and phlegmatic. Disorders of the human body were thought to be caused by an upset in the balance of these humours. 1 Unfortunately his fame and authority were so great that these concepts persisted for 2000 years until overturned after the Renaissance in the 16th century. This was hardly the fault of Aristotle, who was himself no believer in blind obedience to authority.

Aristotle was a great classifier and codifier. In his effort to develop a strong taxonomic scheme, he noticed important similarities and differences between various zoological forms. He arranged these upon a basis of increasing perfection, extending from lower to higher animals. In its way, this was a theory of evolution. 4 He also developed a coherent theory of generation, believing that the mammalian egg was formed in the uterus as a result of the activation of menstrual blood by male semen. 3 “Sex” he wrote “is determined by the male principle already contained in the semen. If this is not strong enough, then the opposite must necessarily come into existence, and the opposite of man is woman.”

Being unable to study the internal structure of the human body, Aristotle turned to the study of animals, founding the science of comparative anatomy. He is said to have dissected over 50 different species, writing: “The inner parts of man are uncertain and unknown, wherefore we must consider those parts of other animals which bear any similarity to those of man.” For his embryological studies he used the chick embryo, describing among other observations the first sign of the embryo, the early development of the heart and great vessels, the beating of the embryo's heart, and the differences between arteries and veins. 1

In Aristotle's day, midwifery was the undisputed province of the midwives, though it was common practice for them to seek assistance from a doctor. Midwives had to be mothers who were past the age of childbearing. One of their functions was to advise men on which girls would be likely to produce the best offspring. They undertook vaginal examinations and were allowed to prescribe drugs, to procure abortion, and to bring on birth prematurely. Another duty was to show the newborn baby to the father. If he was then prepared to recognise the child as his own, he lifted it up for a moment and then handed it back to the midwife. Perhaps their most important responsibility, though, was on when and how to cut the umbilical cord. This was usually delayed until after the afterbirth had been expelled. Any delay in delivery of the placenta was managed by tying weights to the cord (fig 2 ​ 2) ) and by giving the woman powders to make her sneeze violently. 2

An external file that holds a picture, illustration, etc.
Object name is fn74534.f2.jpg

Figure 2  Management of delayed delivery of the afterbirth in ancient Greece. Steady and gentle traction on the umbilical cord is maintained by the baby gradually sinking down on a punctured water bladder.

The following quotations from Aristotle's writings (mainly from Book VII, On the history of animals 6 ) illustrate a few of his teachings on childbirth.

On length of gestation

“Now all other animals bring the time of pregnancy to an end in a uniform way; in other words, one single term of pregnancy is defined for each of them. But in the case of mankind alone of all animals the times are diverse, for pregnancy may be of 7 months' duration or of 8 months or of 9 and still more commonly of 10 (lunar) months, whilst some women go even into the eleventh month.”
“It is natural for other animals also to be born head foremost, but children have their hands pressed against their sides. Directly they come forth they cry out and bring their hands to their mouth. There is evacuation of excrement sometimes at once, sometimes soon, but always within the day, and this excrement is more than accords with the bulk of the child. Women call it meconium; its colour is like blood and it is extremely black and like pitch but after this it already assumes the milk‐like character for the infant draws the breast at once.”

On maternal posture during childbirth

“The woman should lie on her back having her body in a convenient posture. That is, her head and breast a little raised so that she be between lying and sitting. For being so placed she is best capable of breathing and likewise would have more strength to bear her pains than if she lay otherwise …”

On ligation of the umbilical cord

“The division of the cord is the province of the nurse and requires an intelligence that does not blunder, for she must be able not only to give assistance by her dexterity in the difficulty of women's labour but also must be quick‐witted for emergencies, also in the matter of tying the cord for the child. For if the afterbirth is passed at the same time let the cord be tied, away from the afterbirth, with a fillet of wool and it is then cut off from the part above: where it has been tied it grows together and the adjoining part falls off. If the knot comes undone the infant dies of haemorrhage. When the afterbirth does not come away at once but remains inside when the infant is outside, the cord is tied and division made.”

On resuscitation

“Frequently the child appears to be born dead, when it is feeble and when, before the tying of the cord, a flux of blood occurs into the cord and adjacent parts. Some nurses who have already acquired skill squeeze (the blood) back out of the cord (into the child's body) and at once the baby, who had previously been as if drained of blood, comes to life again.”
“The infant does not cry before it comes forth, even if owing to difficulty of labour the woman succeeds in expelling the head but retains the rest of the body inside … Babies after birth for the first forty days do not laugh or cry when awake, but at night they sometimes do both. Even if tickled they do not usually notice it. Most of the time they sleep, but as they grow they keep changing in the direction of more wakefulness. It is evident that they dream but it is a long while before they remember their dreams …”

On lactation

“Women continue to have milk until their next conception; and then the milk stops coming and goes dry, alike in the human species and in the quadrupedal vivipara. So long as there is a flow of milk the menstrual discharges do not take place as a general rule, though the discharge has been known to occur during the period of suckling.”

On neonatal mortality

“Most of the babies are carried off before the seventh day that is why they give the child its name then, as they have more confidence by that time in its survival.”

On maternal love

“This is the reason why mothers are move devoted to their children than fathers: it is that they suffer more in giving them birth and are more certain that they are their own.”

On abortion

“As to the exposure of children, let there be a law that no deformed child shall live. However, let no child be exposed because of excess population, but when couples have too many children, let abortions be procured before sense and life have begun.”

Aristotle was below average height. Sharp and keen of countenance, he was blessed with boundless energy. He was always on the move and collected information from every source. A practical man and a careful observer, he not only sought facts but also methods on how to handle them and put them in order, setting the stage for the development of the scientific method many centuries later. He was high minded and kind hearted and devoted to his family and friends. Calm and without passion he was said to be fair to his enemies and rivals, grateful to his benefactors, and was in fact the embodiment of the moral ideals outlined in his ethical treatises. 1 , 2 , 3 , 4 , 5 The following aphorisms on courage reflect some of his own philosophy: “The ideal man bears the accidents of life with dignity and grace, making the best of circumstances.” “Courage is the first of human qualities because it is the quality which guarantees the others.” “I count him braver who overcomes his desires than him who conquers his enemies; for the hardest victory is over self.” “Dignity consists not in possessing honours, but in the consciousness that we deserve them.”

Let me end with a thought from Aristotle that resonates with respect to the present state of our national health service, dominated as it is nowadays by politicians and managers. He wrote: “Each man judges well the things he knows and of these he is a good judge. And so the man who has been educated in a subject is a good judge of that subject.”

  • Architecture and Design
  • Asian and Pacific Studies
  • Business and Economics
  • Classical and Ancient Near Eastern Studies
  • Computer Sciences
  • Cultural Studies
  • Engineering
  • General Interest
  • Geosciences
  • Industrial Chemistry
  • Islamic and Middle Eastern Studies
  • Jewish Studies
  • Library and Information Science, Book Studies
  • Life Sciences
  • Linguistics and Semiotics
  • Literary Studies
  • Materials Sciences
  • Mathematics
  • Social Sciences
  • Sports and Recreation
  • Theology and Religion
  • Publish your article
  • The role of authors
  • Promoting your article
  • Abstracting & indexing
  • Publishing Ethics
  • Why publish with De Gruyter
  • How to publish with De Gruyter
  • Our book series
  • Our subject areas
  • Your digital product at De Gruyter
  • Contribute to our reference works
  • Product information
  • Tools & resources
  • Product Information
  • Promotional Materials
  • Orders and Inquiries
  • FAQ for Library Suppliers and Book Sellers
  • Repository Policy
  • Free access policy
  • Open Access agreements
  • Database portals
  • For Authors
  • Customer service
  • People + Culture
  • Journal Management
  • How to join us
  • Working at De Gruyter
  • Mission & Vision
  • De Gruyter Foundation
  • De Gruyter Ebound
  • Our Responsibility
  • Partner publishers

research paper on aristotle

Your purchase has been completed. Your documents are now available to view.

book: Aristotle - Contemporary Perspectives on his Thought

Aristotle - Contemporary Perspectives on his Thought

On the 2400th anniversary of aristotle's birth.

  • Edited by: Demetra Sfendoni-Mentzou
  • X / Twitter

Please login or register with De Gruyter to order this product.

  • Language: English
  • Publisher: De Gruyter
  • Copyright year: 2018
  • Audience: Scholars and students of Aristotle, Ancient Philosophy, Classical Studies, Humanities, Aristotle and Contemporary Thought.
  • Front matter: 14
  • Main content: 366
  • Coloured Illustrations: 5
  • Keywords: Aristotle
  • Published: July 23, 2018
  • ISBN: 9783110566420
  • ISBN: 9783110564174
  • Search Menu
  • Sign in through your institution
  • Advance Articles
  • Special Issues
  • Virtual Issues
  • Trending Articles
  • IMPACT Content
  • Author Guidelines
  • Submission Site
  • Open Access Options
  • Self-Archiving Policy
  • Author Resources
  • Read & Publish
  • Why Publish with JOPE?
  • About the Journal of Philosophy of Education
  • About The Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain
  • Editorial Board
  • Advertising & Corporate Services
  • Journals on Oxford Academic
  • Books on Oxford Academic

Issue Cover

Article Contents

  • < Previous

Aristotle, the Action Researcher

  • Article contents
  • Figures & tables
  • Supplementary Data

Marianna Papastephanou, Aristotle, the Action Researcher, Journal of Philosophy of Education , Volume 44, Issue 4, November 2010, Pages 589–595, https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9752.2010.00752.x

  • Permissions Icon Permissions

The Ways of Aristotle: Aristotelian Phronesis, Aristotelian Philosophy of Dialogue, and Action Research. Olav Eikeland. Bern, Peter Lang, 2008. Pp. 560.Pbk. £54.00.

This article discusses Olav Eikeland’s The Ways of Aristotle, a book that takes stock of a whole range of Aristotelian themes and communicates various complex Aristotelian ideas to impressive effect. What is distinctive about the book is, amongst other things, that it provides valuable exegetical material for the kind of interpretation that makes Aristotle’s significance for action research stand out most convincingly. The article approaches the material of the book with an eye to those Aristotelian ideas and connections that usually pass unacknowledged in dominant accounts. Thus, the article aspires to show that it is possible, with the aid of Eikeland’s book, to defend the relevance of Aristotle to present-day educational concerns in hitherto unexplored but henceforth fresh and fertile ways .

The Ways of Aristotle reconstructs Aristotle’s philosophy as political, educational and learning-oriented (p. 450) and deploys its significance for action research innovatively and insightfully. The intersection of the terms ‘political’, ‘educational’ and ‘learning-oriented’ makes Olav Eikeland’s approach to his material valuable for philosophy of education. This is not only because all three of them are central to the discipline, but also, and more, because politics, education and learning are nowadays often connected in a rather impoverished discourse about knowledge- and learning-societies. Thus, a book that enriches this discourse in such a reflective, methodical and masterful way is very welcome.

Email alerts

Citing articles via.

  • Recommend to Your Librarian
  • Advertising and Corporate Services
  • Journals Career Network

Affiliations

  • Online ISSN 1467-9752
  • Print ISSN 0309-8249
  • Copyright © 2024 Philosophy of Education Society of Great Britain
  • About Oxford Academic
  • Publish journals with us
  • University press partners
  • What we publish
  • New features  
  • Open access
  • Institutional account management
  • Rights and permissions
  • Get help with access
  • Accessibility
  • Advertising
  • Media enquiries
  • Oxford University Press
  • Oxford Languages
  • University of Oxford

Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford. It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship, and education by publishing worldwide

  • Copyright © 2024 Oxford University Press
  • Cookie settings
  • Cookie policy
  • Privacy policy
  • Legal notice

This Feature Is Available To Subscribers Only

Sign In or Create an Account

This PDF is available to Subscribers Only

For full access to this pdf, sign in to an existing account, or purchase an annual subscription.

Academia.edu no longer supports Internet Explorer.

To browse Academia.edu and the wider internet faster and more securely, please take a few seconds to  upgrade your browser .

Enter the email address you signed up with and we'll email you a reset link.

  • We're Hiring!
  • Help Center

paper cover thumbnail

Aristotle’s Art of Rhetoric: Translated and with an Interpretive Essay by Robert Bartlett reviewed by Christine J. Basil

Profile image of Christine J Boor (née Basil)

Interpretation

Related Papers

Victoria Kahn

research paper on aristotle

Argumentation

John Poulakos

Classical Quarterly

Tobias Reinhardt

Gregory Sadler

"A set of passages in 1354-1359 of the Rhetoric contain Aristotle’s most explicit discussions of how he conceived the relationships between the different disciplines of rhetoric, politics, dialectic, and ethics. These discussions, while explicit, are brief, and their brevity renders them susceptible to reductive schematization. In this paper, my goal is to elaborate these fertile discussions through three means: close reading of these methodological passages in the Rhetoric; reference to relevant discussions from Aristotle’s other works; and reflection on the dialectical character of Aristotle’s practical philosophy. My main argument is that Aristotle’s practical philosophy, and these passages in particular, offer to and require of his readers a dialectical engagement with the content of the texts (granting that “dialectic” is an equivocal term, I will offer a fuller description in the full paper). I consider four topics more specifically: 1) the relationship between rhetoric and dialectic, as capacities for providing arguments; 2) the ways the discipline of rhetoric shifts into the allied disciplines of politics and ethics; 3) the reasons why rhetoric is always unavoidable in both politics and ethics; 4) how politics and ethics can reciprocally inform rhetoric"

Christof Rapp

Brandon Inabinet

In several recent essays, Brad McAdon has argued that Aristotle's Rhetoric is such a fractured, inconsistent text that it is reasonable to conclude it is not the work of a single author, “Aristotle,” but the work of an editor who combined sections of treatises by several authors. This article challenges McAdon's thesis by reexamining the historical transmission of the Rhetoric and analyzing a central passage in the work—namely Rhetoric 1.4–14 (on the idia or special topics)—that McAdon believes Aristotle could not have written.

Scott R. Stroud

This course is a theoretical-historical review of writings about rhetoric in the Western tradition up through the Enlightenment. It is based upon the assumption that there is no single, stable entity in that tradition called " rhetoric. " Instead, different writers organize that term in relationship to terms referencing other discourses and practices. Each way of situating rhetoric in a world of texts and action is also a way of understanding human experience in general. This course will cover various important figures in the history of rhetoric. We start our investigation with the thinkers from ancient Greece-Plato, Protagoras, Gorgias, Isocrates, and Aristotle. We will examine what they believe rhetoric is, what its value is, and what role it should play in ethics and politics. Important thinkers from the Roman world will also be examined. We'll talk about how Cicero, Quintilian, Christine de Pizan, Immanuel Kant, the American pragmatists and various stoics conceptualized and practiced rhetoric. Attention will be given to the promises and challenges of diversifying the rhetorical canon with female and international voices. We will emphasize primary sources for most of these figures, although I will expose you to selected secondary sources when it seems beneficial. My goals in the class are twofold: (1) I want you to gain a mastery and appreciation for the thought of ancient and classical thinkers " on their own terms. " (2) I want you to become proficient at making and evaluating arguments, both in writing and in speech.

The Nature and Goal of Aristotle's Rhetoric

The Purpose of Aristotle's Rhetoric and the different approachescombined within this work. “The Nature and Goals of Rhetoric”, in: G. Anagnostopoulos (ed.), The Blackwell Companion to Aristotle, Blackwell, Oxford 2009, 579-595

Julene Humes

Rhetoric is a powerful tool, perhaps the preeminent capacity of our sentient species. In this paper, I seek to: (1) Define rhetoric in some of its various associations and usages, (2) depict ways in which it is increasingly used in our modern day with destructive and calamitous consequences, and (3) discuss its ideal manifestation through examination of the works of the father of rhetoric, Marcus Tullius Cicero, and emphasize its use as a tool for the up leveling of humanity. I propose that human beings have a solemn responsibility to make an exacting examination of rhetoric. I propose that the deterioration of language leads to the devolution of humanity. I further propose that the cultivation of expansive vocabulary, the study of great rhetoricians both past and present, and a focused application of the principles of persuasive language will reorient our species towards its evolutionary path. The tyranny of space limitations in this paper makes this a daunting task. In the end, I hope to reveal some touch points that will lead the reader to further seeking and understanding.

Thomas L Pangle

Recent scholars (e.g., Bodéüs 1993; Mara 2000; Smith 2001; Tessitore 1996) have fruitfully proposed that we must strive to understand Aristotle’s distinctive didactic strategy as a writer. By attending more to the interrelationship between the Ethics and the Politics, and to the contrast with modern liberal theorizing on the issue of educative strategy, I show how Aristotle’s rhetorical strategy is at once a reaction to, and thereby a revelation of, his most profound reflections on the fraught relation between theorizing and its political context. The upshot is threefold: a new, more satisfactory comprehension of Aristotle’s manifold educational aims in writing for his diverse intended audience; a deeper insight into Aristotle’s conception of the relation between theory and practice (including publication)—in profound contrast to our Enlightenment liberal conception; and a new guide for how Aristotle’s political treatises ought to be studied and appreciated.

RELATED PAPERS

Historical Studies on Central Europe

Journal of Radiology Case Reports

Placido Romeo

Everson Rodrigo Tatto

European Journal of General Medicine

Hatice Asan

Journal of the American College of Surgeons

Muhammad Umar Butt

APPLIED PHYSICS OF CONDENSED MATTER (APCOM 2019)

Andreea Daescu

Journal of Electron Spectroscopy and Related Phenomena

Vijay Kumar

Argumenta Journal Law

Luana Rosário

Journal of Oral Rehabilitation

Adriana De Stefano

European Journal of Emergency Medicine

door lauwaert

… Facultad Nacional de …

Ronald Alfonso Montañez Valencia

European Journal of Operational Research

Kjell Hausken

Acta Tropica

Patrizia Danesi

Fortune Journals

Behzad Elahi

Maria da Conceição Carvalho

Journal of Cosmology and Astroparticle Physics

Germano Pinto Guedes

Thomas van Gulik

Anne-Maj Gustavsson

JOURNAL OF FACULTY OF ENGINEERING & TECHNOLOGY

Muhammad Omer

Malaria Journal

Andy Dobson

  •   We're Hiring!
  •   Help Center
  • Find new research papers in:
  • Health Sciences
  • Earth Sciences
  • Cognitive Science
  • Mathematics
  • Computer Science
  • Academia ©2024

Catholic University Logo

University Libraries

  • Catholic University Libraries

Aristotle Research Guide

  • Understanding Aristotle
  • Critical Editions and Standard Translations
  • Online Translations
  • Bibliographies and Indices
  • Resources for Reading Aristotle
  • Scholia and Commentaries
  • Manuscripts

Encyclopedias

Dictionaries, understanding aristotle . . . (print resources), understanding aristotle . . . (electronic resources), biographical and background information (greek print sources), dvds which contain aristotle's works.

  • Libraries and Associations

These links contains background information for understanding Aristotle and his works from articles in encyclopedias (print and electronic).  The first two links are online encyclopedia articles (peer reviewed and open access) on Aristotle.

  • Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy consists of peer reviewed articles on all aspects of philosophy including Aristotle. This encyclopedia provides information of scholarly quality freely on the web.
  • Standford Encyclopedia of Philosophy The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy has an article by Christopher Shields on Aristotle which concludes with an extensive bibliography of translations, translations with commentaries, general works, and works cited.
  • Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Craig, Edward (ed). London; New York: Routledge, 1998. B51 .R68 1998 (Religious Studies and Philosophy Library) more... less... This ten volume set contains extensive articles such as "Aristotelianism in Islamic Philosophy", "Aristotelianism in the 17th Century", "Aristotelianism, Medieval", "Aristotelianism, Renaissance", "Aristotle", and "Aristotle Commentators". Each of the articles is accompanied by a list of works (recommended editions and than translations of individual works) and references and further reading. The set is also located at the Reference Desk. The encyclopedia is also available as a CD-ROM in the Religious Studies and Philosophy Library).
  • New Catholic Encyclopedia This link opens in a new window Catholic University of America. 2nd ed. Detroit: Thomson/Gale; Washington, D.C.: Catholic University of America, 2003. BT 6 .N53 2003 (Religious Studies and Philosophy and Reference) New Catholic Encyclopedia (Volume 1) contains an article by J. Owens on Aristotle which concludes with a bibliography.
  • Encyclopedia of Philosophy This link opens in a new window Edwards, Paul. New York : Macmillan: Free Press; London: Collier Macmillan, 1967. B41 .E56 1967a (Religious Studies and Philosophy Library, Reference, and Stacks) This encyclopedia (available online and in print) is the English-language reference source for philosophy and has been the cornerstone of the philosophy reference shelf. The extensive article on Aristotle by Stephen Menn includes a comprehensive bibliography.
  • Encyclopedia of Rhetoric This link opens in a new window This encyclopedia provides a comprehensive survey of the latest research and the foundational teachings in this broad field. It synthesizes a vast amount of knowledge from classics, philosophy, literature, literary theory, cultural studies, speech and communications, and discusses basic concepts and themes throughout rhetoric. Even though the encyclopedia does not have an article on Aristotle himself; this encyclopedia contains articles (such as Topics and Pathos) which mention Aristotle, his writings, and his influence. A search for Aristotle returns 104 results.
  • Aristotle Dictionary Kiernan, Thomas P. (ed.). New York: Philosophical Library, 1962. PA3926 .Z8 1962 ( Humanities Greek and Latin) more... less... This book provides a lengthy overview of Plato's works and main ideas (more than 150 pages) as well as a dictionary of quotations from Aristotle's works.
  • The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy Audi, Robert (ed.). 2nd ed. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 1999. B41 .C35 1999 (Religious Studies and Philosophy Library) more... less... This dictionary consists of lengthy and comprehensive articles on Aristotle and other topics such as commentaries on Aristotle and virtue ethics.
  • The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy Blackburn, Simon. 2nd ed. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press, 2005. B41 .B53 2005 (Mullen Library stacks) more... less... This dictionary provides a shorter article on Aristotle and other topics such as arete and Aristotelianism than the article found in The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy.
  • Dictionary of Philosophy and Religion: Eastern and Western Thought Reese, William L. new and enl. ed. Atlantic Highlands, NJ: Humanities Press, 1996. B41 .R43 1996 (Religious Studies and Philosophy Library) more... less... This dictionary contains numerous cross-references in its articles. Even though the dictionary does not contain exhaustive information on topics, its article on Aristotle is rather lengthy.
  • A Dictionary of Philosophy Mautner, Thomas. Oxford, UK; Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Reference, 1996. B41 .M38 1996 (Religious Studies and Philosophy Library) more... less... This dictionary is for individuals who are new to studying philosophy - articles on important thinkers such as Aristotle and the vocabulary found in philosophy are included. The dictionary's article on Aristotle is shorter than the article found in The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy.
  • A Dictionary of Philosophy Lacey, A. R. 3rd ed. London: Routledge, 1996. B41 .L32 1996 (Religious Studies and Philosophy Library) more... less... This dictionary contains a short article on Aristotle.
  • Dictionary of Literary Biography This link opens in a new window . Provides nearly 16,000 biographical and critical essays on the lives, works, and careers of the world's most influential literary figures from all eras and genres such as Aristotle. Aristotle appears in Volume 176: Ancient Greek Authors. (A Bruccoli Clark Layman Book. Edited by Ward W. Briggs, University of South Carolina. The Gale Group, 1997, pp. 55-76).
  • Oxford Classical Dictionary This link opens in a new window . The Oxford Classical Dictionary has an article by Martha C. Nussbaum on Aristotle which concludes with a bibliography (text, translations, commentaries, and general).
  • Oxford Handbook of Aristotle Christopher Shields, Oxford University Press, 2012.
  • A Companion to Aristotle Anagnostopoulos, Georgios (ed.). Blackwell Companions to Philosophy Chichester, UK; Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell, 2009. B485 .C59 2009 (Stacks) more... less... This book contains 40 chapters which highlight central topics found in Aristotle's works as a whole (substance, essence, cause, etc.).
  • The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle Barnes, Jonathan (ed.). Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press, 1995. B485 .C35 1995 (Religious Studies and Philosophy Library) more... less... This book provides philosophical criticism on Aristotle's life and his works; the book's focus is Aristotle as a philosopher. The book concludes with suggestions for reading and a comprehensive bibliography (introductory, juvenilia, logic, philosophy of science, science, psychology, metaphysics, ethics, rhetoric and poetics, and politics).
  • A Companion to Aristotle's Politics Keyt, David and Fred D. Miller. Oxford, UK; Cambridge, MA: B. Blackwell, 1991. JC71.A7 A75 1991 (Stacks) more... less... This book contains 15 chapters discussing aspects of Aristotle's Politics such as man, private property, distributive justice, oligarchy, and political change.
  • Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Aristotle on Ethics Hughes, Gerald J. Routledge Philosophy Guidebooks London; New York: Routledge, 2001. B430 .H84 2001 (Stacks) more... less... This book provides a discussion of Aristotle's terminology, interpretation controversy of Aristotle's writings, and the impact of Aristotle's Ethics on contemporary moral philosophy.
  • Routledge Philosophy Guidebook to Aristotle and the Metaphysics Politis, Vasilis. Routledge Philosophy Guidebooks London; New York: Routledge, 2004. B434 .P65 2004 (Stacks) more... less... This book provides an introduction to reading and understanding Aristotle's Metaphysics, especially the main arguments.
  • Aristotle: a Guide for the Perplexed Vella, John A. Guides for the Perplexed London; New York: Continuum, 2008. B485 .V45 2008 (Stacks) more... less... This book contains Aristotle's key ideas and their influence on western philosophy in chapters such as science, being or substance, nature, soul, and success.
  • Greek Philosophy A Collection of Texts with Notes and Explanations Volume II Vogel, C. J. De. 3rd ed. Leiden, Netherlands: E. J. Brill, 1967. B 165 .V87 v.2 1967 (Religious Studies and Philosophy Library) more... less... Volume II, Aristotle, the Early Peripatetic School and the Early Academy, contains actual Greek passages from Aristotle as well as notes in English. Book III is entirely on Aristotle (life, works, Physics, Metaphysics, Nicomachean Ethics, Rhetoric, Poetics, and much more). These books are also available in the Greek and Latin Reading Room and the Stacks.
  • The Oxford Companion to Philosophy Honderich, Ted (ed.). 2nd ed. Oxford; New York: Oxford University Press, 2005. B51 .O94 2005 (Religious Studies and Philosophy Library) more... less... This book contains articles on most philosophical terms and provides articles on Aristotle and Aristotelianism.
  • A Companion to the Philosophers Arrington, Robert L. (ed.) Blackwell Companions to Philosophy Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers, 1999. B 72 .C595 1999 (Religious Studies and Philosophy Library) more... less... This book contains 193 essays including an essay on Aristotle which concludes with a bibliography.
  • A Companion to Ethics Singer, Peter (ed). Blackwell Companions to Philosophy. Oxford, UK; Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Reference, 1991. BJ1012 .C62 1991 (Religious Studies and Philosophy Library) more... less... This book contains 47 essays on ethics which includes discussion on Aristotle and topics such as arete, practical reason, virtue, and Nichomachean Ethics.
  • Greek Thought: a Guide to Classical Knowledge Brunschwig, Jacques and Geoffrey E.R. Lloyd (eds.). Translated by Catherine Porter. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2000. DF78 .S2813 2000 (Stacks) more... less... This book contains an essay on Aristotle which concludes with a bibliography (texts and translations and studies) and related articles. Illustrations are included.
  • People with online papers in philosophy David Chalmers maintains People with online papers in philosophy which provides links to online papers. Philosophy papers on Aristotle are found under "Ancient" (Ancient Greek Philosophy).
  • Paideia Project On-Line The Paideia Project On-Line contains philosophy papers in its archives, including papers on Aristotle. You can look for Aristotle under "Ancient Philosophy" heading or type Aristotle's name in the search box. Not all of the papers are in English.
  • Modern Interpretation of Ancient Logics Klaus Glashoff (former professor at the University of Hamburg, Germany) maintains this website. He provides papers (in PDF) on Aristotle and logic.
  • Princeton/Stanford Working Papers in Classics Princeton/Stanford Working Papers in Classics contains papers discussing Plato, Aristotle, Socrates, and others. more... less... Select "The Papers" Select "Classical Philosophy"
  • Svidae Lexicon Adler, Ada. (ed.). Lipsiae: in aedibvs B. G. Tevbneri, 1928-38. PA5365 .A23 1928 (Greek and Latin Reading Room) more... less... This five volume set is the Suda in print. The Suda is in Greek while the Preface is in Latin. Volume 1 contains entries for Aristotle.
  • Classical Greek Philosophy [videorecording] Viddisc. 00528 (Central Reserve Audiovisual) more... less... This program addresses core topics in ancient philosophy such as freedom and fate, permanence and change, happiness, the nature of the cosmos, and the immortality of the soul. Concepts are presented as articulated by key figures including Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, Heraclitus, Pythagoras, and the Milesian and Eleatic philosophers -- in combination with quotations drawn from Plato’s Republic, Aristotle’s Physics, and other influential sources -- make this program an excellent tool for building a solid understanding of Western philosophy.

Ask for these DVDs at the Circulation Desk.

  • Ethics [videorecording] : what is right? Viddisc. 00111 (Central Reserve Audiovisual) more... less... Harvard University’s Frances Kamm, Rutgers University’s Larry Temkin, and Richard Sorabji, emeritus professor of philosophy at King’s College, London, describe the three major categories of ethics: metaethics, applied ethics, and normative ethics. Also included are virtue theory, divine command theory, utilitarian theory, and duty theory. Plato’s Republic, Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, and Kant’s Grounding for the Metaphysics of Morals are considered along with the contributions of Epicurus, Hume, Bentham, Hegel, Marx, Nietzsche, Max Weber, G.E. Moore, and John Rawls.
  • << Previous: Manuscripts
  • Next: Reviews >>
  • Last Updated: Apr 10, 2024 12:25 PM

Aristotle Research Paper Topics

Academic Writing Service

This page provides a comprehensive list of Aristotle research paper topics divided into ten distinct categories, each offering a deep dive into different aspects of Aristotle’s vast body of work and philosophical principles. Aristotle’s philosophies, spanning from metaphysics and ethics to politics and rhetoric, have profoundly influenced various facets of human existence and intellectual thought. This article serves as a thorough guide, highlighting the importance of Aristotle and the multitude of research paper topics encompassed by his legacy. Additionally, we will introduce iResearchNet’s writing services, a crucial resource for students wishing to commission a custom research paper on any topic related to Aristotle. With features such as expert degree-holding writers, in-depth research, custom formatting, and a money-back guarantee, iResearchNet stands as a trusted and user-friendly solution for students’ academic needs.

100 Aristotle Research Paper Topics

The vast range of Aristotle’s contributions to various fields of knowledge, from philosophy and science to arts and politics, makes him a fascinating subject for academic research. This page provides a comprehensive list of Aristotle research paper topics divided into ten distinct categories, each offering a deep dive into different aspects of Aristotle’s thoughts and influences.

Academic Writing, Editing, Proofreading, And Problem Solving Services

Get 10% off with 24start discount code.

  • The concept of substance in Aristotle’s Metaphysics.
  • Aristotle’s theory of potentiality and actuality.
  • The role of the unmoved mover in Aristotle’s metaphysical framework.
  • Aristotle on the nature of reality: Being and becoming.
  • A comparison of Aristotle’s and Plato’s metaphysics.
  • The concept of form and matter in Aristotle.
  • Aristotle’s views on the existence of God.
  • The role of teleology in Aristotle’s Metaphysics.
  • Aristotle’s critique of Plato’s theory of forms.
  • The concept of change in Aristotle’s Metaphysics.
  • The concept of the golden mean in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics.
  • Aristotle’s view on the nature of happiness.
  • The role of virtue in Aristotle’s ethical theory.
  • Aristotle’s views on the relationship between ethics and politics.
  • A comparison of Aristotle’s and Kant’s ethical theories.
  • The concept of phronesis (practical wisdom) in Aristotle’s ethics.
  • Aristotle on the nature of moral responsibility.
  • The role of friendship in Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics.
  • Aristotle’s views on the nature of the good life.
  • The concept of eudaimonia in Aristotle’s ethical theory.
  • Aristotle’s view on the role of the citizen in the state.
  • The concept of the best government according to Aristotle.
  • Aristotle’s critique of Plato’s Republic.
  • The role of the middle class in Aristotle’s political theory.
  • Aristotle’s views on slavery and its role in society.
  • The concept of justice in Aristotle’s Politics.
  • Aristotle’s views on the nature of law and its role in society.
  • The role of education in Aristotle’s political theory.
  • Aristotle’s views on the relationship between the individual and the state.
  • A comparison of Aristotle’s and Machiavelli’s political theories.
  • The role of ethos, pathos, and logos in Aristotle’s Rhetoric.
  • Aristotle’s views on the nature of tragedy in his Poetics.
  • The concept of catharsis in Aristotle’s theory of tragedy.
  • Aristotle’s influence on later rhetoricians and literary theorists.
  • A comparison of Aristotle’s and Plato’s views on poetry.
  • The role of imitation (mimesis) in Aristotle’s Poetics.
  • Aristotle’s views on the role of the artist in society.
  • The concept of the tragic hero in Aristotle’s Poetics.
  • Aristotle’s influence on Renaissance rhetoric and poetics.
  • The role of plot (mythos) in Aristotle’s theory of tragedy.
  • Aristotle’s contributions to biology and its influence on later science.
  • Aristotle’s views on the nature of the universe in his Physics.
  • The concept of the four causes in Aristotle’s natural philosophy.
  • Aristotle’s contributions to the development of logic.
  • The influence of Aristotle’s scientific writings on medieval science.
  • Aristotle’s views on the nature of time and space.
  • The role of observation and experience in Aristotle’s scientific method.
  • Aristotle’s influence on the development of medieval astronomy.
  • A comparison of Aristotle’s and Galileo’s views on physics.
  • Aristotle’s views on the nature of life and its origins.
  • Aristotle’s views on the nature of the soul in his De Anima.
  • The concept of nous (intellect) in Aristotle’s philosophy of mind.
  • Aristotle’s views on perception and its role in knowledge.
  • The concept of the active intellect in Aristotle’s philosophy of mind.
  • A comparison of Aristotle’s and Descartes’ views on the mind-body problem.
  • Aristotle’s views on the nature of consciousness.
  • The role of imagination in Aristotle’s philosophy of mind.
  • Aristotle’s views on the nature of thought and its relationship to language.
  • The influence of Aristotle’s philosophy of mind on later philosophers.
  • Aristotle’s views on the nature of mental states and their causes.
  • Aristotle’s influence on Thomas Aquinas and medieval scholasticism.
  • The reception of Aristotle’s works in the Islamic world.
  • Aristotle’s influence on the development of Renaissance philosophy.
  • The role of Aristotle in the development of modern science.
  • A comparison of Aristotle’s and Hegel’s dialectical methods.
  • Aristotle’s influence on the development of modern ethics.
  • The reception of Aristotle’s works in the 19th and 20th centuries.
  • Aristotle’s influence on the development of modern logic.
  • The role of Aristotle in the development of analytic philosophy.
  • Aristotle’s influence on contemporary philosophy.
  • A comparison of Aristotle’s and Plato’s views on the nature of reality.
  • The influence of Plato on Aristotle’s thought.
  • A comparison of Aristotle’s and Plato’s views on ethics.
  • The influence of Aristotle’s works on later Platonic philosophers.
  • A comparison of Aristotle’s and Plato’s views on politics.
  • The influence of Aristotle on the development of Neoplatonism.
  • Aristotle’s views on Plato’s philosophy of mind.
  • A comparison of Aristotle’s and Plato’s views on art and beauty.
  • The influence of Aristotle’s rhetoric on Plato’s dialogues.
  • The concept of the beautiful in Aristotle’s philosophy.
  • Aristotle’s views on the role of art in society.
  • The concept of imitation (mimesis) in Aristotle’s aesthetics.
  • Aristotle’s views on the nature of music and its effects on the soul.
  • The concept of catharsis in Aristotle’s aesthetics.
  • A comparison of Aristotle’s and Kant’s views on aesthetics.
  • Aristotle’s influence on later theories of art and beauty.
  • The role of tragedy in Aristotle’s aesthetics.
  • Aristotle’s views on the nature of comedy.
  • The influence of Aristotle’s aesthetics on Renaissance art.
  • The relevance of Aristotle’s ethics in the modern world.
  • Aristotle’s influence on contemporary theories of virtue ethics.
  • The relevance of Aristotle’s political theory in the contemporary world.
  • Aristotle’s influence on modern theories of rhetoric and communication.
  • The relevance of Aristotle’s philosophy of mind in the contemporary philosophy of mind.
  • Aristotle’s influence on contemporary theories of metaphysics.
  • The relevance of Aristotle’s scientific method in modern science.
  • Aristotle’s influence on contemporary theories of aesthetics.
  • The relevance of Aristotle’s views on education in the contemporary world.
  • Aristotle’s influence on modern theories of law and justice.

Aristotle’s works have left an indelible mark on the intellectual history of the Western world and continue to be influential in a variety of fields, from philosophy and science to politics and the arts. The plethora of Aristotle research paper topics listed above showcases the depth and breadth of his thought and its ongoing relevance in the modern world. Whether you are interested in his contributions to metaphysics, ethics, politics, science, art, or his influence on later thinkers, there is a wealth of research topics to explore. And remember, this is just a starting point – the world of Aristotle research paper topics is as vast and varied as the philosopher’s own works.

The Range of Aristotle Research Paper Topics

Aristotle, born in 384 BCE in Stagira, a Greek colony in Macedonia, is undoubtedly one of the most influential figures in the history of Western philosophy. A student of Plato and the tutor of Alexander the Great, Aristotle’s contributions spanned across various fields, including metaphysics, ethics, politics, science, and aesthetics. His comprehensive system of thought laid the foundation for much of Western philosophy and science for nearly two millennia. The prolific nature of his works and the broad spectrum of topics he covered make Aristotle research paper topics incredibly varied and relevant even in contemporary discourse.

Aristotle’s Significance in Philosophy

Aristotle’s significance in philosophy is monumental. His work in metaphysics, which involves the study of the nature of existence and reality, is foundational. His concept of ‘substance,’ and distinctions between ‘form’ and ‘matter,’ ‘potentiality’ and ‘actuality,’ are fundamental to metaphysical inquiry. His ethical thought, centered around the concept of ‘eudaimonia’ or flourishing, has played a significant role in the development of ethical theory. In politics, his analysis of different forms of government, the role of the citizen, and the importance of a well-rounded education are still discussed and debated today. His work in the natural sciences, though largely outdated by modern standards, laid the groundwork for empirical observation and classification. In the realm of aesthetics, his analysis of tragedy in ‘Poetics’ is a foundational text that continues to be studied by students of literature and drama. This vast array of contributions means that Aristotle research paper topics can range from the deeply philosophical to the practically applied.

Broad Range of Aristotle Research Paper Topics

The broad range of research paper topics that Aristotle offers is a testament to his comprehensive approach to understanding the world and human existence. In metaphysics, Aristotle research paper topics could delve into his concept of substance, his argument for the existence of a prime mover, or his critique of Plato’s theory of forms. Aristotle’s ethics offers a wealth of research topics, from his concept of the golden mean to his views on friendship and its role in a flourishing life. Aristotle’s politics provides a fertile ground for research on topics such as his views on the best form of government, the role of the middle class, and the relationship between ethics and politics.

In the realm of rhetoric and poetics, Aristotle research paper topics could explore his concepts of ethos, pathos, and logos, his theory of tragedy, or his views on imitation and its role in art. Aristotle’s contributions to science provide a historical perspective on the development of scientific thought, with research topics including his classification of living beings, his views on the nature of the universe, or his contributions to the development of logic. Aristotle’s philosophy of mind offers a rich array of research topics, from his views on the nature of the soul to his theories on perception and consciousness. The influence of Aristotle on later philosophers is another area ripe for exploration, with research topics including his impact on medieval scholasticism, the reception of his works in the Islamic world, or his influence on modern philosophy.

In the area of art and beauty, topics could range from Aristotle’s views on the nature of beauty, the role of art in society, or the concept of catharsis in his theory of tragedy. Finally, modern interpretations and applications of Aristotle’s ideas provide a wealth of research topics, from the relevance of his ethics in the modern world to his influence on contemporary theories of rhetoric, philosophy of mind, metaphysics, aesthetics, or law and justice. The broad range of Aristotle research paper topics showcases the depth and breadth of his thought and its ongoing relevance in the modern world.

Aristotle’s contributions to various fields of knowledge are incredibly vast and have left a lasting impact on Western thought. His works have influenced numerous disciplines, from philosophy and science to politics, art, and more. This broad spectrum of influence provides a wide array of Aristotle research paper topics that are not only historically significant but also relevant to contemporary debates and discussions. Whether you are interested in delving into the intricacies of his metaphysical concepts, exploring his views on ethics and politics, analyzing his contributions to rhetoric and poetics, or examining his influence on later philosophers and contemporary thought, there is a wealth of Aristotle research paper topics to choose from.

In conclusion, the importance of Aristotle in the history of philosophy and the wide range of potential research areas he offers cannot be overstated. His comprehensive approach to understanding the world and human existence has left a lasting legacy that continues to be explored and debated by scholars and students alike. Therefore, selecting an Aristotle research paper topic offers an opportunity to engage with the works of one of the most influential thinkers in human history and to contribute to the ongoing discourse surrounding his ideas.

iResearchNet’s Custom Writing Services

iResearchNet is a professional writing service company dedicated to providing high-quality academic assistance to students across the globe. With a particular emphasis on Aristotle research papers, our expert writers are well-equipped to help students tackle a variety of topics related to the great philosopher’s extensive body of work. Our team is composed of skilled writers holding advanced degrees in philosophy and related fields, ensuring that each research paper is well-researched, well-argued, and written with the highest level of academic integrity.

  • Expert Degree-Holding Writers : Our team consists of writers with advanced degrees in philosophy and related fields, ensuring a high level of expertise in Aristotle research paper topics.
  • Custom Written Works : Each paper is written from scratch, tailored to the specific requirements and guidelines provided by the client.
  • In-depth Research : Our writers conduct thorough research using a wide range of reputable sources to provide a comprehensive analysis of the chosen topic.
  • Custom Formatting : We provide custom formatting in various citation styles, including APA, MLA, Chicago/Turabian, and Harvard.
  • Top Quality : Our commitment to quality is unmatched. Each paper undergoes a rigorous quality check to ensure it meets the highest academic standards.
  • Customized Solutions : We offer customized solutions to meet the unique needs of each client, whether it’s a complete research paper, literature review, or any other component of the paper.
  • Flexible Pricing : Our pricing structure is flexible and transparent, with no hidden charges. We offer a range of pricing options to suit different budgets.
  • Short Deadlines : We understand the importance of meeting deadlines and offer a range of delivery options, including the ability to deliver high-quality papers within as short as three hours.
  • Timely Delivery : We pride ourselves on our punctuality. Each paper is delivered on time, without compromising on quality.
  • 24/7 Support : Our customer support team is available 24/7 to assist with any questions or concerns.
  • Absolute Privacy : We respect our clients’ privacy and confidentiality. All personal information and transaction details are kept secure.
  • Easy Order Tracking : Our user-friendly online platform allows clients to easily track the progress of their orders in real-time.
  • Money-Back Guarantee : We offer a money-back guarantee to ensure complete satisfaction. If, for any reason, the final paper does not meet your expectations, we will refund your money.

Ready to Order Your Custom Aristotle Research Paper?

Don’t miss out on the opportunity to receive expert assistance on your Aristotle research paper. With our team of skilled, degree-holding writers, we guarantee a top-quality, custom-written research paper tailored to your specific needs. Say goodbye to stress and let iResearchNet handle your Aristotle research paper needs. Order now and enjoy the benefits of our professional writing services!

Secure Your Success with iResearchNet

Writing an Aristotle research paper can be a daunting task, given the depth and breadth of the philosopher’s work. However, with iResearchNet’s professional writing services, you can rest assured that your research paper is in capable hands. From our expert degree-holding writers to our commitment to quality, customized solutions, and flexible pricing, we offer a range of features designed to meet your needs. Moreover, our commitment to timely delivery, 24/7 support, absolute privacy, easy order tracking, and a money-back guarantee ensures a seamless and satisfying experience from start to finish. So, why wait? Take advantage of iResearchNet’s services for your Aristotle research paper needs and order your custom paper today!

ORDER HIGH QUALITY CUSTOM PAPER

research paper on aristotle

SEP home page

  • Table of Contents
  • Random Entry
  • Chronological
  • Editorial Information
  • About the SEP
  • Editorial Board
  • How to Cite the SEP
  • Special Characters
  • Advanced Tools
  • Support the SEP
  • PDFs for SEP Friends
  • Make a Donation
  • SEPIA for Libraries
  • Entry Contents

Bibliography

Academic tools.

  • Friends PDF Preview
  • Author and Citation Info
  • Back to Top

Aristotle’s Biology

Aristotle is properly recognized as the originator of the scientific study of life. This is true despite the fact that many earlier Greek natural philosophers occasionally speculated on the origins of living things and much of the Hippocratic medical corpus, which was written before or during Aristotle’s lifetime, displays a serious interest in human anatomy, physiology and pathology. And Plato has Timaeus, in the eponymous dialogue, devote a considerable part of his speech to the human body and its functions (and malfunctions). Nevertheless, before Aristotle, only a few of the Hippocratic treatises are both systematic and empirical, and their focus is almost exclusively on human health and disease.

By contrast, Aristotle considered the investigation of living things, and especially animals, central to the theoretical study of nature. Constituting roughly 25% of the extant corpus, his zoological writings provide a theoretical defense of the proper method for biological investigation; and they provide a record of the first systematic and comprehensive study of animals. There was nothing of similar scope and sophistication again until the 16 th century. In the nineteenth century the great anatomist Richard Owen introduced a two lecture survey of Aristotle’s zoological studies by declaring that “Zoological Science sprang from his [Aristotle’s] labours, we may almost say, like Minerva from the Head of Jove, in a state of noble and splendid maturity” (Owen 1992, 91). Before examining this remarkable achievement, a few words about its creator are in order. [ 1 ] .

1. Life and Work

2. aristotle’s philosophy of science, 3. caveat lector, 4. philosophy of biology.

  • 5.1 The History of Animals as a Report of the results of a Hoti -Investigation

5.2 From Inquiry to Understanding; from hoti to dioti .

6. a concluding puzzle, selected texts, translations, commentaries, secondary sources on aristotle’s biology, other internet resources, related entries.

Aristotle was born in Stagira on the northern Aegean coast in 384BCE. His father Nicomachus was physician to King Amyntas III of Macedon, and his mother was of a wealthy family from the island of Euboea. He was sent at the age of 17 to Athens, where he studied in Plato’s Academy for 20 years, until Plato’s death in 347. By then he had developed his own distinctive philosophical ideas, including his passion for the study of nature. He joined a philosophical circle in Assos on the coast of Asia Minor, but soon moved to the nearby island of Lesbos where he met Theophrastus, a young man with similar interests in natural science. Between the two of them they originated the science of biology, Aristotle carrying out a systematic investigation of animals, Theophrastus doing the same for plants.

In 343 Aristotle was asked by Philip II of Macedon to tutor his son Alexander. By 335 he had returned to Athens, now under the control of his former student Alexander. With Theophrastus he founded a ‘school’ in a public sanctuary known as the Lyceum. He headed the Lyceum until the death of Alexander the Great in 323. With anti-Macedonian feelings running high in Athens, Aristotle retired to his mother’s birthplace. He died there in 322BCE.

The surviving corpus of Aristotle derives from medieval manuscripts based on a 1 st century BCE edition. There were no commentaries on the biological works written until they were collectively translated into Arabic. The first appearance of Aristotle’s biological writings in the West are Latin translations, by Michael Scot, of an Arabic edition, which forms the basis of Albertus Magnus’ De animalibus . In the 13 th century, William of Moerbeke produced a Latin translation directly from the Greek. The first printed editions and translations date to the late 15 th century, the most widely circulated being that of Theodorus Gaza. In addition to the three works traditionally referred to as History of Animals ( HA ), Parts of Animals ( PA ) and Generation of Animals ( GA ), there are a number of briefer ‘essays’ on more specialized topics: On animal motion , On animal locomotion , On respiration , On life and death , On youth and old age , On length and shortness of life , On sleeping and waking , On the senses and their objects (the last six being included in the so-called Parva naturalia ). Whether one should consider De Anima ( On the soul ) part of this project or not is a difficult question. What is certainly clear, however, is that there are important connections between the theoretical approach to the relationship between body and soul defended in that work and the distinctive way that Aristotle approaches the investigation of animals.

In order to understand Aristotle’s distinctive approach to the study of living things, it is imperative to situate it within his natural philosophy and his philosophy of science. The first book of Aristotle’s Parts of Animals is, in fact, largely devoted to doing just that, and after a brief discussion of Aristotle’s general views about scientific inquiry and explanation, we will turn to it.

In sections 4, 5 and 6, we will explore the ways in which Aristotle systematically organizes and explains an extraordinary body of information about animal anatomy, physiology and development. But Aristotle was able to accomplish what he did in zoology because he had given a great deal of thought to the nature of scientific inquiry. How does one progress from the superficial and unorganized state of everyday experience toward organized scientific knowledge? To answer this question, you need a concept of the goal to be achieved, and Aristotle developed such a concept in his Prior and Posterior Analytics (henceforth abbreviated as APr . and APo ., respectively). The goal of scientific inquiry, he argued, was a system of concepts and propositions organized hierarchically, ultimately resting on knowledge of the essential natures of the objects of study and certain other necessary first principles. These definitions and principles form the basis of causal explanations of all the other universal truths within the domain of study. Those other universal truths should identify attributes belonging to a subject per se , in virtue of that subject’s nature. The example he uses when he introduces his account of scientific demonstration to illustrate such propositions is from geometry: having interior angles equal to two right angles belongs to all and only triangles in virtue of their being triangles ( APo . I 4, 5). This attribute belongs to all equilateral triangles as well—not, however, because they are equilateral, but because they are triangles . Thus scientific knowledge of such a proposition, knowledge that displays the reason why any triangle has this property, must explain why this property belongs to triangles as such . The explanation, of course, will appeal to the essential character of three-sided rectilinear plane figures, i.e. to what it is to be a triangle.

The second book of the Posterior Analytics discusses how to achieve this goal of scientific knowledge, one central concern being how knowledge of essences, expressed in definitions, is related to explanations expressed in the form of causal demonstrations. Plato had formulated a famous paradox of inquiry in his dialogue Meno : either you know the object of your inquiry, in which case inquiry is unnecessary; or you don’t know the object of your inquiry, in which case inquiry is impossible ( Meno 80d5-e5). Aristotle reminds us of this paradox in the first chapter of the Posterior Analytics , but his full solution only emerges in book II. There, he argues that perceptual experience gives us a grasp of the target of inquiry that, though it does not count as scientific knowledge, does serve to direct further inquiry. He begins the discussion by presenting us with a claim about how objects of inquiry are linked to objects of scientific knowledge.

The things about which we inquire are equal in number to the things we know scientifically. We inquire about four things: the fact , the reason why , if something is , what something is . ( APo . II 1, 89b23–25)

Aristotle conceives of these four inquiries as paired , and there is a natural sequence in each pair. Knowing that some state of affairs is the case, we can inquire into the reason why it is the case.

When we know the fact we inquire about the reason why (e.g., knowing that it is eclipsed or that the earth moves, we inquire into the reason why it is eclipsed or why the earth moves). ( APo . II 1, 89b29–31)

Similarly, if we conclude an inquiry into whether something exists, we can go on to investigate its nature, what it is.

And having come to know that it is, we inquire what it is (e.g.: Then what is a god? Or what is a man?). ( APo . II 1, 89b34–35)

The examples reveal a distinction that structures much of the discussion for the next ten chapters. For it looks as if ‘factual’ inquiries concern whether some attribute belongs to some subject (movement to the earth, eclipse to the moon), and the search for the reason why will be a search for the causal explanation of the attribute belonging to that subject. By contrast, it looks like the move from ‘if’ to ‘what’ is a move from establishing the existence of some subject (‘god’, ‘man’) to establishing what it is.

However, the distinction is not, it turns out, so clear-cut. Having begun to illustrate the distinction between inquiry if or whether something is and what it is with the question ‘whether there is or is not a centaur or a god’, he then characterizes the knowledge achieved as ‘knowing that it is’. And in the second chapter, he begins to link the two sequences of inquiry by means of his syllogistic concept of “middle term,” the term that is common to the two premises in a syllogistic proof.

Thus it results that in all our research we seek either if there is a middle term or what the middle term is . For the middle term is the cause, and this is in every case what is sought. ( APo . II 2, 90a7–9)

That is, in any valid syllogistic inference, the middle term shared by the premises is the warrant for the conclusion. In scientific explanation, however, the middle term must also identify the cause of the fact given in the conclusion—what that term identifies is the causal link between the subject and attribute. To use another of his common examples, if we seek to explain the periodic sound of noise in the clouds, the middle term must identify the cause of the connection between that noise and those clouds. Moreover, on Aristotle’s account of the relationship between causal demonstration and scientific definition, knowing the cause of thunder is at the same time knowing the essence of thunder, what thunder really is.

There is a difference between saying why it thunders and what thunder is. In the one case you will say: Because the fire is extinguished in the clouds. But: What is thunder?—A noise of fire being extinguished in the clouds. Hence the same account is given in different ways: in one way it is a continuous demonstration, in the other a definition. ( APo . II 10, 94a4–8)

In the APo ., Aristotle returns regularly to such standard examples of natural phenomena as thunder and eclipses—but he also, and importantly, provides an extended biological example, the seasonal loss of leaves in broad-leafed plants. [ 2 ] In ch. 16, Aristotle imagines an inquiry that begins with questions such as ‘Why do fig trees and grape vines lose their leaves?’. The model answer is ‘Because they are both broad-leafed.’ That is, the inquiry seeks some other feature, common to both kinds, related to the target of inquiry, the seasonal loss of leaves. The ‘because’ is, however, preliminary—it is best to see being broad-leafed as a step toward causal explanation. Chapter 17 picks up the example, in the context of arguing that basic scientific inquiry seeks, wherever possible, co-extensive predications, which those between leaf loss and fig trees, or leaf loss and grape vines, are not. The candidate major premise, however—‘Whatever is broad-leafed loses its leaves’— does identify a co-extensive relationship between subject and predicate. It may thus serve as a proper scientific explanandum , and ‘broad-leafed’ can serve to identify a kind, all and only the members of which lose their leaves. [ 3 ] Thus, the middle term of the preliminary explanation becomes the subject of a more basic, co-extensive predication. The cause of broad-leafed trees losing their leaves will, then, be something more fundamental about broad-leafed trees, here identified as the solidification of moisture at the leaf juncture, which can thus serve as the middle term in a causal explanation of this fact. But it will also serve as part of a definition of leaf loss.

The middle is the account of the first major term [i.e. the predicate in the conclusion], for which reason all the sciences come about through definition. ( APo . II 17, 99a22–23)

That is, we will have, if our research goes well, an account of what loss of leaves is. Along the way a process of identifying the kind, all and only the members of which will lose their leaves due to sap coagulation, is assumed. Yet the Analytics provides no systematic discussion about whether there are general criteria for identifying these basic scientific kinds. As we will see, this is the topic of one of the most interesting sections of On the Parts of Animals , book I.

There are two quite different questions we need to ask about how these ideas about inquiry and explanation in the Analytics are related to Aristotle’s investigations of animals: first, how is the philosophy of biology presented in PA I related to the general account of explanation, definition and inquiry in the Posterior Analytics [ 4 ] ; and second, to what extent do the treatises reporting his actual investigations of animals conform either to his general account of scientific knowledge and inquiry in APo ., or to the norms regarding the study of animals laid down in PA I. The remainder of this entry will be organized around these two questions.

First some preliminary remarks are in order about what we are—and are not—discussing. It seems obvious, once stated, that the actual activity of studying animals is different from the activity of writing or teaching about animals based on that study. We have access to a number of Aristotle’s systematically organized writings on animals; we do not have direct access to his actual investigations. Some authors studied by historians of science discuss, in their written work, the methods they used to gather the information and work out their theoretical ideas and even provide ‘diaries’ describing their day-to-day studies—Aristotle is not one of them. Nor did anyone else report observing Aristotle carrying out his studies. There are reasonable inferences we can make from his writings; for example that he consulted with bee-keepers, fishermen and sponge divers, that he (or someone under his guidance) performed a great many dissections on a wide variety of animals, that there were at least some diagrams produced based on these dissections, and so on. Moreover, on the question of how he reasoned to specific explanations we can make some reasonable inferences from things he says about proper methods of biological inquiry. But it is important to keep in mind that we are studying texts that present, in a highly structured and theoretical manner, the results of an actual investigation, the details of which we know very little.

It is also unclear what is the intent of the texts we do have that report on these investigations. It is sometimes said they are ‘lecture notes’. That seems pretty clearly wrong; they are too carefully written and structured. But it does seem clear, from cross-references, that some of them were to be studied in a certain order, and this order may conform to a course of study in the Lyceum. Interestingly, while all of the other biological treatises refer for further information to ‘the animal inquiries’,that is to something like the History of Animals that has come down to us, often in conjunction with ‘the dissections’, our History of Animals has no references to the other, explanatory studies. This suggests that the ‘inquiries and dissections’ had a different function in such a course of study, perhaps something akin to ‘reference works’.

Finally, it is also worth recalling that the series of treatises we have was likely compiled hundreds of years after Aristotle’s death from whatever he left. It seems unlikely we will ever be able to determine the exact relationship between the so-called ‘Andronican’ edition, the likely source of our texts, and what was produced during Aristotle’s lifetime.

These three caveats place constraints on what I can reasonably claim to be doing. I will be discussing the treatises that report the results of Aristotle’s investigations of animals. I will assume that the texts that have been passed down to us reflect what he wrote on this subject, and that the cross-references in those texts are his and reflect his own views about how these various studies are related to each other.

On the Parts of Animals , book I ( PA I) begins by outlining its purpose, which is to establish a set of standards for judging natural investigations (639a15). Its five chapters pursue this purpose, discussing the appropriate level of generality for such studies, the modes of causality and of necessity to be used in biological explanations, the relation of form to matter in living things, the proper method of logical division for this subject matter, the means of identifying kinds and their activities at the proper level of abstraction, and much more. Two sorts of evidence support the conclusion that this book is intended to deal with problems and questions that arise in the application of Aristotle’s general philosophy of science, found in the Posterior Analytics , to his theoretical investigation of living nature.

The first kind of evidence consists of passages introducing his biological investigations that appear to make explicit reference to the account of scientific knowledge in APo . The following passage from the History of Animals (a better though less familiar translation would be Animal Inquiries ), for example, suggests that the entire biological project is organized in accordance with the theory of inquiry developed in APo . II. This passage comes near the end of chapter six in the first book of HA . After five chapters in which Aristotle lays out the kinds of similarities and differences among animals to be studied and sketches the ways in which they are to be investigated, he makes the following programmatic statement about the investigation to come, and where it fits in the entire scientific study of animals.

These things, then, have now been said by way of outline to provide a taste of what things need to be studied, and what it is about them that needs to be studied, in order that we may first grasp the differences and the attributes belonging to all animals. After we do this, we must attempt to discover the causes. For it is natural to carry out the investigation in this way, beginning with the inquiry into each thing; for from these inquiries it becomes clear both about which things ( peri hôn ) the demonstration ( tên apodeixin ) should be and from which things ( ex hôn ) it should proceed. ( HA I 6, 491a7–14)

The natural way to proceed, then, is to begin with inquiry ( historia ), with the aim of grasping the differences between, and attributes of, all the animals; and then to attempt to discover their causes. This is natural because, given that our goal is demonstrative understanding, we want to end up with a clear distinction between the facts to be explained (the peri hôn ) and their explanation (the ex hôn ). This statement echoes the summary, in APo. I 10, of the components of demonstrative knowledge:

Nevertheless there are by nature these three [components of demonstrative knowledge]: that about which ( peri ho ) it proves, what it proves, and those things from which ( ex hôn ) it proves. (76b21–22)

The History of Animals characterizes itself as establishing the attributes and the differences that belong to all animals, and claims that by carrying out this inquiry we are prepared to go on to search for the causes. Indeed, he appears to suggest that a successful historia or factual inquiry will prepare us to grasp the difference between those facts that need to be explained and those that will be invoked in our explanations. In the language of the Posterior Analytics : HA establishes the fact , e.g. that all animals with lungs have windpipes, or that all cetacea have lungs and are viviparous, typically seeking to identify groups by means of discovering co-extensive differentiae with the aid of the method of division. [ 5 ] The proper use of division, moreover, will give clear indications of which predications are basic and which derivative. Works such as Parts of Animals or Generation of Animals , on the other hand, seek to establish the reason why—the cause—of the fact. If Aristotle is following the method described in the Analytics , these causal explanations should at the same time point us to essential definitions of what it is to be a windpipe or to be viviparous. It is a question currently much debated whether definition was, in fact, an explicit goal of HA or simply a consequence of the explanatory goal clearly identified in the above passage from HA I 6; and if so, whether definitions of animal kinds were sought, or only definitions of their attributes. As we will see, there are a number of chapter summaries in the explanatory treatises that make a point of claiming that both an explanation of why a part is found in those animals that have it, and an account of what that part is, have been provided; but one must work very hard to reconstruct any definitions of animal kinds in those treatises. [ 6 ]

A number of texts in Aristotle’s causal investigations reinforce the message of HA I 6, stressing that the preliminary work of inquiries that establish and organize the facts at various levels of generality has been accomplished; and they regularly refer to something like what is reported in our HA as the place to look for the results of this preliminary work. Two explicit statements to that effect follow, one from the beginning of his study of the causes of the differences in animal locomotion, one from the beginning of his study of the causes of the differences among the parts of animals.

Clearly there needs to be a study of all of these questions about animal locomotion and any others of the same kind; for that ( hoti ) these things are thus is clear from our inquiries into nature (t ês historias tês phusikês ); the reason why ( dioti ) must now be investigated. ( IA 1, 704b7–10)
From which parts and from how many parts each of the animals is constituted has been exhibited more clearly in the inquiries about them ( en tais historiais tais peri autôn ); it is the causes owing to which each animal has this character that must now be examined, on their own and apart ( chorisantas kath’hauta ) from what was said in the inquiries. ( PA II 1, 646a8–12)

Each of these passages explicitly describes the study of animals with which Aristotle is engaged in the language of Aristotle’s theory of research in APo . II 1. Indeed, the passage from HA I 6 does so by insisting that the natural method to use is to first get clear on the differences and attributes to be demonstrated (‘establish the fact that …’) before going on to find the causes (‘the reason why, i.e. the cause’) to be appealed to in these demonstrations. Animal inquiries ( historiai ) are a kind of hoti inquiry—that is, the History of Animals presents the facts to be explained, organized so as to be prepared for causal demonstration. [ 7 ]

The IA and PA , on the other hand, refer to themselves as pursuing a causal inquiry into the reason why the various kinds of animals are differentiated as they are, and they acknowledge that they are able to do this precisely because the factual investigation into the locomotion and parts of animals has been accomplished. In both cases Aristotle emphasizes the distinction on which we are focused, perhaps in order to remind his readers of his philosophy of scientific research.

There is a second line of evidence, quite independent of these programmatic statements, which leads to the same conclusion. The topics covered in PA I take the form of specifications of the central topics of the Posterior Analytics . These specifications are required because animals are [a] complex unities of matter (body) and form (soul); [b] arise by a complex process of development; [c] the end—that for the sake of which the development occurs— is both causally and definitionally prior to that process; [d] a distinctive kind of necessity, conditional necessity, is operative; and [e] a special method of multi-differentiae division is required. Such a discussion is required by the fact that although the Posterior Analytics intends its epistemic standards to be applicable to natural science – as is clear from the many examples drawn from natural science in book II – it provides no details as to how this application is to be accomplished.

What, then, does PA I tell us about the proper way to investigate animals? Aristotle begins by posing a problem about how to identify the proper objects of investigation. Should we begin by studying the features of groups close to the level of perception, such as human beings, horses, dogs and such, or should we look for attributes that ‘belong in common according to kind, and then later study their distinctive attributes’ (639b4–5). He notes that since there are many attributes that are common to many of these more concrete kinds, focusing our study on them will have the result of our repeating ourselves—much as if, to use an example from APo II discussed in Section 2, we were to remain at the level of ‘olive trees lose their leaves’, ‘grape vines lose their leaves’. Among these common attributes, Aristotle distinguishes those that seem not to differ across the kinds that have them (he cites respiration and death) from those that are ‘ distinctive in form ’ such as locomotion. As he puts it: “it is apparent that locomotion is not one in form, because flying, swimming, walking, and crawling differ” (639b1–2). Aristotle deals with this question, so reminiscent of APo . I 4–5, in PA I 4, but only after he has introduced a new way of thinking about differentiae and division appropriate for investigating animals. After discussing his recommendations regarding the use of logical division in biology, we will return to look at his answer.

Animals are complex structures organized so as to be able to perform an integrated set of functions and activities; yet the Posterior Analytics provides one with very little guidance as to how to apply its norms to such things. Again PA I, and especially chapters 1 and 5, appears designed to provide that guidance. It seeks to establish [a] the priority of goal-causation to motive-causation, [b] the priority of the study of an animal’s form (which, he argues, should be identified with its soul) to the study of its material constituents (i.e. its body), and [c] the presence of a special kind of necessity operative where goals and form take priority, namely hypothetical or conditional necessity (cf. PA I 1, 640a10–641a32, 642a1–31).

The argument is complicated in virtue of its manner of presentation. First, it is a narrative in which Aristotle gradually develops his own views by exposing the errors of those who investigated nature before him; it is structured as presenting an alternative to views expressed by Empedocles and Democritus, and as in the spirit of Socrates (642a24–31). Second, as is so typical of him, what initially may appear to be three separate narratives turn out to be a single, complex case for emphasizing the study of form, teleological explanation, and conditional necessity when studying living things. Form, in the case of living things, turns out to be the capacity to perform living functions such as nutrition, perception, or locomotion, i.e. soul; and thus the form of a living thing is causally prior to the matter, because it is the goal for the sake of which the parts of the animal—its matter—come to be and exist. This, in turn, provides us with the appropriate way to understand ‘conditional necessity’—parts and the processes that produce them do not necessitate the outcome; on the contrary, the outcome necessitates that the developmental processes bring about the parts that are necessary for the organism to live its life, and do so in a temporally and spatially coordinated manner (cf. GA II 4, 740b19–34; II 6, 743a16–36).

Chapters 2 and 3 have a similar narrative structure. Gradually, a positive theory of biological division emerges from the ashes of a detailed critical analysis of those (Plato and certain of his students) who “attempt to grasp the particular by dividing the kind into two differences” (642b5), a practice he finds in “the written divisions” (642b11), perhaps a reference to divisions we find in some of Plato’s later dialogues, or perhaps to lost works by other members of Plato’s Academy. The method he is criticizing combines two basic techniques that lead to things being grouped together that are fundamentally different and things being grouped separately that are fundamentally similar: dichotomy and division by non-essentials. Dichotomy is the method of dividing the more general differentia into two exhaustive alternatives, which often entails that one of the alternatives is simply the privation of the other (winged, wingless). Division by non-essentials involves dividing a prior differentia-class by means of an unrelated difference. For example, you might first divide animals into winged and wingless, and then winged animals into wild and tame.

I mean the sort of thing that results by dividing animals into the wingless and the winged, and winged into tame and wild, or pale and dark. Neither tame nor pale is a difference of winged; rather each is the origin of another difference, while here it is incidental. (643b19–22)

To avoid the problems created by this dichotomous and arbitrary method, Aristotle recommends a method that divides each wider differentia by more and more determinate forms of that differentia (wings into forms of wing, beaks into forms of beak), and does so simultaneously on as many differentiae as are correlated at a given level of universality.

Rather, one should try to take animals by kinds, following the lead of the many in demarcating a bird kind and a fish kind. Each of these has been defined by many differences, not according to dichotomy. (643b9–12)

Thus, if all birds have beaks, feathers, wings of a sort, are bipedal, etc. , the biologist needs to perform the proper sort of division on all of these in order to grasp the various sub-kinds of bird. This will not, of course, give us demonstrative knowledge; but it will help us to grasp the co-extensively correlated features, at each level of specificity, that are the proper things about which to seek demonstrative knowledge.

An interesting feature of this extended criticism of dichotomous, arbitrary division and the development of a systematic, multi-differentiae alternative is that it takes for granted the ‘naturalness’ of certain kinds that ‘the many’ have identified. As he says above, ‘these [birds and fish] have been defined by many differences’; earlier he had said that the terms ‘bird’ and ‘fish’ name a ‘similarity’, a group of animals that are ‘alike in kind’ that dichotomous division inappropriately tears apart (642b13–19). During the discussion of division there is very little clarification of what underlies this notion of similarity or likeness in kind. However, armed with a method of division suited to the study of animals, the discussion quickly turns to the question of what it is that makes it appropriate to treat all birds or all fish as a single kind, and to the specification of rules for identifying other such kinds. What ‘bird’ and ‘fish’ name are, he claims, kinds with “common natures, and forms not very far apart” (644b2–3). Prior to understanding these kinds through a scientific account of this common nature, we can—as the Posterior Analytics argues—grasp these kinds, i.e. grasp that all birds have a common nature. [ 8 ] We do this by noting that they have many general differences that vary in measurable ways—by the more and less, as he puts it.

…[these kinds] are correctly defined in this way. For those animals that differ by degree and the more and the less have been brought together under one kind, while those that are analogous have been kept apart. I mean, for example, that bird differs from bird by the more or by degree (for one has long feathers, another short feathers), while fish differs from bird by analogy (for what is feather in the one is scale in the other). (644a16–22)

It is with this very topic of different degrees of similarity and difference of parts that the Historia Animalium begins, extending this way of characterizing similarity and difference immediately to differences in activities, ways of life and traits of character. ( HA I 1, 486a5–487a13) This is, then, clearly a discussion of how one achieves ‘knowledge of the fact’, rather than ‘knowledge of the reason why’.

The closing section of PA I (treated since the Renaissance as its fifth chapter) is often thought of as having two, essentially unrelated parts. And there is some justification for this; if one were to remove the first half of the chapter, one would be left with an argument the flows quite naturally out of the conclusion of chapter 4. At that point, Aristotle states that once one has made an initial division of the attributes that belong to all the animals per se , the next step is to attempt “to divide their causes,” after which he applies the analysis of sameness and difference from the previous discussion of parts to the activities performed by these parts. He then closes the discussion by arguing that the differences we find in animal parts are to be explained by reference to differences found among their activities. Thus a proper division of activities is a division of the causes of the parts of animals.

Nevertheless, a good case can be made that this ‘chapter’ forms a coherent whole, a sort of culmination of the book. It begins with perhaps the best known passage in Aristotle’s biological works, a stirring and beautifully crafted encomium to the joys of studying animals, even the most lowly. An elegant introduction divides natural beings into those that are eternal and those that partake of generation and perishing, noting that there are attractions to studying both: though access to information about the former is limited, he likens it to “…a chance, brief glimpse of the ones we love”; on the other hand the latter, perishable things “take the prize in respect of understanding because we know more of them and know them more fully” and they are “more of our own nature” (644b23–645a3). He then elaborates on the value of the study of the living things around us. It is a passage worth quoting in full.

Since we have completed stating the way things appear to us about the divine things, it remains to speak about animal nature, omitting nothing in our power, whether of less or greater esteem. For even in the study of animals disagreeable to perception, the nature that crafted them likewise provides extraordinary pleasures to those able to know their causes and who are by nature philosophers. Surely it would be unreasonable, even absurd, for us to enjoy studying likenesses of animals—on the ground that we are at the same time studying the art, such as painting and sculpture, that made them—while not prizing even more the study of things constituted by nature, at least when we can behold their causes. For this reason we should not be childishly disgusted at the examination of the less valuable animals. For in all natural things there is something marvelous. Even as Heraclitus is said to have spoken to those strangers who wished to meet him but stopped as they were approaching when they saw him warming himself at the oven—he bade them to enter without fear, ‘For there are gods here too’—so too one should approach research about each of the animals without disgust, since in every one there is something natural and good. For what is not haphazard but rather for the sake of something is in fact present most of all in the works of nature; the end for the sake of which takes the place of the good. If someone considered the study of the other animals to lack value, he ought to think the same thing about himself as well; for it is impossible to look at that from which mankind has been constituted—blood, flesh, bones, blood vessels, and other such parts—without considerable disgust. Just as one who discusses the parts or equipment of anything should not be thought of as doing so in order to draw attention to the matter, nor for the sake of the matter, but rather in order to draw attention to the overall shape (e.g. to a house rather than bricks, mortar, and timbers); likewise one should consider the discussion of nature to be referring to the composite and the overall substantial being rather than to those things which do not exist when separated from their substantial being. ( PA I 5, 645a4–36)

Readers, often carried away by the rhetoric of this passage, might fail to notice that there is a compelling argument here, with two key conclusions. The first is that, while studying the Sun, Moon, starts and planets may be a noble pursuit, if scientific understanding is your goal, you are much more likely to achieve it in the study of animals and plants: “…anyone wishing to labor sufficiently can grasp many things about each kind…we know more of them and we know them more fully…they are nearer to us and more of our own nature…” (excerpted from 644b29–645a3). The second is that if one has the proper philosophical focus, then one realizes that the somewhat unpleasant task of dissecting blood vessels and the like, is a means to understanding that for the sake of which and soul , those objects of inquiry argued to be primary in chapter 1. For the lesson of chapter 1 is that understanding living matter is achieved primarily by means of an understanding of the functional goals served by an animal’s parts, discovering what each of its parts is for, what it contributes to the life of the animal. This is the philosophical way to investigate animals, and by doing so you learn the value of an animal’s parts and activities to its life.

The remainder of the chapter, therefore, recommends approaching the activities associated with animals and their parts in a manner exactly analogous to the approach to the study of parts recommended in chapter 4 (645b1–14); and it concludes with a schematic discussion of the variety of teleological relationships that hold among parts, between parts and their activities, and among activities. Aristotle encourages us to conceive of these relationships in a yet more unified way, as a single complex relationship between a single complex activity (living, I suppose) and a single complex instrument, the animal’s body. (645b15–36)

In the first book of On the Parts of Animals , then, we have a systematic philosophy of biology, which in many respects seems to provide what is missing in the Analytics regarding the application of its program to the study of living nature. But does Aristotle’s biological practice carry through on this program? It is worthwhile keeping that question in mind as we survey those books that report the results of Aristotle’s animal studies. To those books we now turn.

5. Aristotle’s Biological Practice

5.1 the history of animals as a report of the results of a hoti -investigation.

As we saw earlier, Aristotle introduces his systematic study of the differences and attributes of animals as a hoti -investigation, a factual investigation preliminary to the search for causal demonstrations. By studying it, then, we ought to be able to develop a rich picture of what this theoretically motivated, preliminary stage of investigation aims to achieve, and perhaps a glimpse of what such an investigation entails.

As many studies, following up on the pioneering work of David Balme (1961, 1987b) have now established, the History of Animals ( HA ) is a work that from first to last displays and builds upon multi-differentiae division of animal differences (see Gotthelf 1988, 1997b; Lennox 2001b, chs. 1, 2; Pellegrin 1986). It is organized as a study of four kinds of animal differences first mentioned in HA ’s first chapter as the principal objects of study (at 486b22–487a14)—differences in parts (the topic of Books I–IV), in modes of activity and ways of life (those related to generation in Books V-VI--and human generation in IX--others in Book VII) and in characters (Book VIII). These in turn are sub-divided; for example, discussion of the non-uniform parts (organs, as we say) of animals with blood (I 7-III 1) is followed by that of their uniform parts (tissues, III 2–22). A discussion of the parts of animals without blood then concludes the discussion of differences in parts (IV 1–8). Book IV concludes with a discussion of differences in sensory faculties, voice, and differences related to sex. [ 9 ]

It is only once Aristotle begins to distinguish differences among, say, uniform parts that various groupings of animals play an important role in organizing the discussion. And in so far as there are relatively stable general groupings of animals, these are identified by noting their possession of stable correlations among differentiae—for example, there are a large number of different animals all of which have wings, feathers, beaks, and two fleshless legs, and this group of animals has been given the designation ‘bird’. [ 10 ] In other cases, such groups have not been generally recognized, and Aristotle simply refers to them by means of some of their most important correlated differences—the four-legged and live-bearing animals, for example, corresponding to our land mammals (with one important exception).

What is clear from the practice of the History of Animals is both the value of division and its limitations. Division by itself does not provide you with the axes of division; rather they are presupposed. Division does not give you animal kinds; as we saw in the previous section, one needs to turn to PA I 4 and HA I 6 for Aristotle’s thoughts on how those kinds are established. Something besides division is needed in order for a researcher to recognize theoretically significant kinds, such as cephalopods or cetaceans. Why group animals together based on their possession of four legs and the ability to give birth to living offspring (rather than eggs)? Certainly each of these traits is the product of a division, one of modes of locomotion and one of modes of reproduction. But those divisions do not tell you that animals with four legs that bear living young constitute a scientifically significant group.

A second limitation of division is its indifference to the distinction between causally fundamental characteristics and proper attributes, to use the language of the Analytics . Yet, being able to distinguish these is absolutely fundamental to Aristotelian science. A careful comparative study of the History of Animals , on the one hand, and works such as On the Parts or On the Generation of Animals , on the other, provides insight into how Aristotle understands and deploys this distinction in his actual scientific practice. And as we have seen above, Aristotle draws explicit attention to its importance for his biological investigations in a number of key texts within those investigations themselves. To study in detail the interplay between definition, causal demonstration and division in the biology is to see Aristotle working through just those problems which form the central question of Posterior Analytics II—how precisely are definition, causal demonstration and division related to one another in the quest for, and achievement of, scientific understanding?

It is impossible to present even a hint of the richness of the empirical content of the Historia Animalium here. Before going on to a discussion of the works that report the results of Aristotle’s causal investigations of animal parts and animal generation, however, two examples of reports from HA are provided for comparison with corresponding discussions in PA and GA . The first example discusses the organs of respiration in blooded animals; these are the first internal organs discussed after Aristotle has concluded his review of their external parts. Here is how he introduces that discussion.

So, then, the number and character of the external parts of the blooded animals and how they differ from one another has been stated. We must now discuss how the internal parts are situated, first in the blooded animals. As many as ( hosa ) are four legged and live-bearing all ( panta ) have an esophagus and windpipe, arranged just as in human beings; it is also arranged similarly in as many of the four legged animals as lay eggs, and in the birds; but they differ in the forms ( tois eidesi ) of these parts. Generally, all and only ( panta hosa ) those receiving air by inhaling and exhaling in every case ( panta ) have a lung, windpipe and esophagus; and the position of the esophagus and windpipe is alike in all, but the organs are not, while the lung is neither alike in all nor is it positioned in a like manner. And again as many as ( hosa ) have blood all ( panta ) have a heart… . But not all [blooded animals] have a lung, for instance fish do not, nor any other animal there might be that has gills. (505b23–506a12, excerpts)

There are a number of features in this passage that are common throughout the Historia Animalium and provide insight into its methods and aims. First is the syntactically redundant linguistic pattern hosa…panta (“as many as...all”), variants of which are common in this treatise. Aristotle appears to use the sentence form “As many as are X, all have Y” for a quite specific reason. It is not just to note a universal correlation; it is to do so while leaving the extension of the correlation open—a brilliant methodological innovation. New animals with the correlation can be discovered, but the generalization will not change, since it is about the universal correlation among differentiae—in this case internal organs—not about the kinds that exemplify it. It appears that when Aristotle intensifies the expression by writing panta hosa , as he does once here, he means to signal a convertible universal, an ‘entailment’ as we would say. Aristotle first lists a number of distinct groups, all the members of which have the three organs being discussed, windpipe, lung and esophagus. Then, using the term ‘generally’ to signal what he is about to do, he identifies a differentia that all these groups have in common, and which is coextensive with these three organs—inhaling and exhaling air. The inductive pattern has the following form:

‘As many as are P all have Y ; As many as are Q all have Y … . Generally, all and only those that are X (a feature common to P , Q …) have Y ’.

By going on to note that as many as have blood have a heart, he implicitly is warning the reader about a potential false inference one might draw from the examples so far: that all blooded animals have a lung. He mentions fish as an example of blooded animals without a lung, but immediately identifies the relevant differentia: ‘those blooded animals that have gills do not have these organs [the lung and its associated parts]’. He is careful not to restrict the universal to a kind—the relevant correlation is with gills , in whichever animals they might be found.

While the inductive strategy of this work, directing us to high-level, convertible universals is, I hope, now clear, it is also important to note what is absent from this passage. Aristotle rarely in this work claims any of these correlations is necessary , or that others are impossible . He does not distinguish features that are part of the essence of a kind from others that are mere attributes; and he typically avoids any hint of causal explanation . All of this is to be expected, given the methodological guidelines for historia that we discussed earlier— historia is preliminary to causal investigation and prepares us for it. In the passage we are currently considering, for example, it is striking that he notes the convertible correlation between lung, windpipe and esophagus, on the one hand, and inhaling and exhaling of air, on the other, but does not claim that two of the organs are present for the sake of breathing. (In fact, the word for ‘breathing’ is never used!) Though he uses the term ‘nature’ regularly in HA , he does not , as he does so often in his causal investigations, claim that nature does nothing in vain, or that it always does what is best for each organism. Nor does he talk about the parts of an animal as its material nature, nor about its living capacities as aspects of its formal nature. Indeed there is virtually no mention of the matter-form distinction in HA . It is only when we turn to the various biological treatises devoted to causal investigation that this language associated with the search for definitions and demonstrations comes to the fore.

The aim of this brief analysis of one small passage is to convey a taste of the methodological depth and complexity of this great scientific treatise, so often misunderstood as a poorly organized compendium of nature lore. I’ll conclude this section with one more example, from the books dealing with generation, so that we may compare it with a corresponding discussion in De Generatione Animalium .

HA V-VI discuss all aspects of animal generation, moving from consideration of differences in modes and timing of copulation and reproduction to the actual process of generation (or ‘development’, as we more often say). As in his discussion of parts, he moves through the various blooded kinds and then discusses generation in bloodless kinds and from identifying the universals common to all members of a group to identifying the peculiarities of more specific kinds. At HA VI 3, having previously described the common and peculiar characteristics of copulation in birds, he turns to recording his observations of the development of the chick at the critical fourth day after the egg has been laid.

Generation from the egg occurs in an identical manner in all birds, though the time taken to termination varies, as we have said. In the case of the hen, the first signs of the embryo are seen after three days and nights; in larger birds it takes more time, in smaller birds less. During this time the yolk travels upwards to the point of the egg—that is where the starting point of the egg is and where it opens up, and the heart is no bigger than just a small blood-spot in the white. This spot beats and moves as though it were alive; and from it, as it grows, two vein-like vessels with blood in them lead on a twisted course to each of the two surrounding membranes. A membrane with bloody fibers already surrounds the white of the egg, at this time coming from the vessel-like channels. A bit later the body can also be distinguished, at first very small and pale. The head is apparent, and its eyes, very swollen; and this continues for a long time, for it is later that they contract and become smaller. (561a4–21)

He begins with a wide generalization about all birds, followed by a ‘more and less’ correlation between the size of the bird and the rate of development. This device allows Aristotle to use the careful description of the chick egg opened on day four as a universal description of development; the reader is licensed to infer that the same stage of development will occur in all birds, but may occur either earlier or later, depending on whether they are larger or smaller than the domestic chicken. Aristotle’s description of this classic experiment led to its being repeated many times in the Renaissance. [ 11 ] Anyone who has seen modern films of the chick at this stage of differentiation can appreciate the accuracy of Aristotle’s description, especially when one takes into account the size of the chick embryo at this stage of growth.

For Aristotle, ‘ historia ’, the scientific organization of information about animals—serves the goal of causal explanation; and, as I discussed in section 4., explanation by reference to goals and functions is the primary form of causal explanation in biology.

On the Parts of Animals II-IV presents Aristotle’s attempt to provide causal explanations for the sort of information one finds organized in HA I-IV, information about the uniform and non-uniform parts of animals. ( PA I, it will be recalled, is a discussion of the norms that are needed to guide the scientific investigation of animals; see section 4, above.) Here, I will be narrowly focused on just a couple of passages in PA II-IV, but will begin with a very brief sketch of its overall structure. It begins ( PA II 1–2) with a careful and complex discussion of the causal relationships between uniform and non-uniform parts (roughly, this distinction corresponds to our distinction between bodily fluids and tissues and organs), stressing the teleological priority of the whole organism to the parts, and among parts the priority of the non-uniform to the uniform. PA II 3–10 then discusses the uniform parts, beginning with that out of which all the others are nourished, blood, and ending with flesh, bone, and analogous materials (nail, horn, hoof). From II 10 to III 3, Aristotle discusses the external parts of blooded animals associated with the head such as eyes, ears, nose and mouth. But when he gets to the neck, he turns to the internal parts, and from III 3 to IV 4 he discusses the ‘innards’ of the blooded animals, parts such as heart, lung, liver, kidneys, and so on. From IV 5 to 9 he discusses the parts, both internal and external, of the ‘bloodless’ animals, i.e. the crustaceans, testaceous mollusks, cephalopods and insects. Finally, at IV 10, he returns to the external parts associated with the torso and limbs of the live bearing and egg laying quadrupeds (10–11), birds (12), and fish (13); and ends by discussing a number of animals that ‘dualize’ between being land-dwellers and water dwellers or flyers.

In order to compare the methods of this treatise with the discussion of the parts in HA , it will be useful to look briefly at PA III 3, a discussion of the lung, windpipe and esophagus, the part discussed in the passage from HA II quoted in section 5.1, above.

Not all animals have a neck, but only those with the parts for the sake of which the neck is naturally present—these are the windpipe and the part known as the esophagus. Now the larynx is present by nature for the sake of breathing; for it is through this part that animals draw in and expel air when they inhale and exhale. This is why those without a lung have no neck, e.g. the kind consisting of the fish. The esophagus is the part through which nourishment proceeds to the gut; so that animals without necks manifestly do not have an esophagus. But it is not necessary to have the esophagus for the sake of nutrition; for it concocts nothing. And further, it is possible for the gut to be placed right next to the position of the mouth, while for the lung this is impossible . For there needs first to be something common like a conduit, which then divides in two and through which the air is separated into passages—in this way the lung may best accomplish inhalation and exhalation. So, then, the organ connected with breathing from necessity has length; therefore it is necessary for there to be an esophagus between the mouth and the stomach. The esophagus is fleshy, with a sinuous elasticity— sinuous so that it may dilate when food is ingested, yet fleshy so that it is soft and yielding and is not damaged when it is scraped by the food going down. (664a14–34)

I have highlighted the language of nature, necessity, possibility (and impossibility), and being for the sake of in this passage in order to highlight the contrast with the discussion of the same organic correlations in the corresponding HA passage. Here the goal is explanation —parts are present and have the character they do primarily due to the conditional necessity imposed by the organism’s functional requirements. One sees here the Aristotle that so impressed the great French naturalist Georges Cuvier: Aristotle is not only systematically discussing the adaptive functions of each of these organs; he is also displaying the complex way in which the internal parts of animals constitute an organic system .

The lack of names for animal kinds is also noteworthy; as in the corresponding passage from HA II, fish are mentioned once as an instance of blooded animals that lack the organs in question; but the stress throughout is on this particular system of organs in whichever blooded animals have them. Aristotle’s goal is to explain why it is that certain animals have these organs, and why it is that, if they have one of these organs, they must have the others. Some, but not all, of the explanations specify the function for the sake of which the parts are present; and even the material nature of the tissues, whether fleshy or sinuous, may be explained in functional terms. This discussion also displays a hierarchy of teleological connections of the sort described at the close of PA I 5, 645b28–33—one activity is present for the sake of another more basic one; a part that performs a subordinate activity is present for the sake of a part that performs a more important activity. Inhaling and exhaling are for the sake of respiration (which is for the sake of cooling the blood); a windpipe is present for the sake of transporting air to and from the lung; a neck is present to protect the windpipe.

For reasons that will become clear, the relationship between the books of the Historia Animalium dealing with generation and On the Generation of Animals ( GA ) is somewhat more complex. GA has a reasonably clear organization of its own; but its central (though not only ) project of explaining the causal roles of the male and female in sexual generation and the causality of embryological development raises a host of topics and problems well beyond the scope of HA . But a study of how the two works are related is nonetheless illuminating. This discussion of Aristotle’s biological practice will thus close by considering the causal explanation of embryological development and in particular the explanation for the early appearance of the heart, with a final look at the application of this explanation to the case of embryonic birds.

As I noted earlier, taken on its own terms, GA has a reasonably clear structure. Here again, as with PA II-IV, I will begin with a brief sketch of its overall structure, before focusing narrowly on its method as applied to one problem. It begins (715a1–18) by noting that it will explain two sets of facts left unexplained in PA : the differences among the parts related to generation; and the generation of the parts generally. Though he acknowledges that some animals do not have males and females, he treats sexual generation as his central topic. Initially he provides a theoretically ‘neutral’ account of the distinction: the male is what generates in another, the female what generates in itself (716a14–15). It is not until late in book I that he begins to develop his own detailed theory of their distinctive contributions to generation.

The first 13 chapters characterize the reproductive organs in the males and females of blooded animals, while 14–16 do the same for the bloodless animals that have males and females. Beginning in chapter 17, the discussion turns to the relevant uniform parts related to generation, sperma (roughly ‘seed’) and milk, but the discussion of milk is postponed until book IV. This immediately raises the contentious issue of whether both male and female contribute sperma , and if both, then what the nature of their respective contributions is. This is a large part of the discussion from I 17-II 5, one of the most difficult stretches of text in the Aristotelian corpus, and the one on which our attention will be focused. But to continue our overview: the remainder of book II (from chapter 5 on) discusses the causes of the embryological development of live-bearing animals, while the egg-laying animals are the primary focus in book III, which closes with a discussion of animals that are not sexually generated, including those that arise ‘spontaneously.’ GA IV turns to the development of inherited differences within kinds, beginning with the most important intra-specific difference for his theory of generation, the difference between male and female. From there it moves on to family resemblance, differences in the number of offspring produced and to the causes of deformities. GA V aims to explain ‘more and less’ variations within kinds that appear late in development and that may be fully accounted for by identifying material level causal interactions—differences within a kind in the color, texture or density of a part, for example.

The remainder of this discussion will focus on the general causal theory of animal generation developed in the first half of GA II. [ 12 ] In the closing chapters of book I, Aristotle argues that both the male and female contributions are formed from a ‘useful residue’ of blood by a concocting process, the male’s being more fully concocted than the female’s. From this point on the male’s contribution is typically termed gonê (semen), and the female’s katamenia (menses). Aristotle is not entirely consistent, however: occasionally he uses the generic term sperma for the male contribution and explicitly contrasts it with katamenia (727a27–30); while at other times he refers to katamenia as a sort of sperma (728a26–29).

The two contributions are variously described. The male contributes a source of movement or dunamis (‘power’ or ‘potential’), which, as the argument unfolds, turns out to be a special sort of capacity to heat present in the semen’s pneuma or air, which is part of its nature. (This gets fully worked out in GA II 2–3) The semen itself is mere a vehicle for delivering this heating capacity; the male makes no material contribution to the offspring. The female contributes what might be called ‘prepared matter’; all it needs is the presence within it of the heating capacity from the male and it begins a more or less lengthy and complicated developmental process, which Aristotle analogizes to a sort of automaton performing a complex set of coordinated movements once it is set in motion.

He relies at several points in the argument on an analogy with crafts, such as house building:

In animals that emit semen the nature in the male uses the semen as an instrument possessing active movement, just as the tools are moved in things that come to be by craft; for the movement of the craft is somehow in these tools. (730b20–23)

This obscure analogy gradually gets unpacked in the first four chapters of GA II. The general principle common to art and nature is this:

As many things as come to be by nature or by art come to be by means of a being in actuality from that which is potentially such as that being. (734b22–23)

It is the prepared portion of the female’s katamenia that is potentially such as the contributor of semen is actually. And the semen conveys to it a movement or power, such that “when the movement ceases each of the parts comes to be and is ensouled (734b24–25).” That is, in embryological development, each part emerges within a system of parts that is organized to provide nutrition for its growth, and that is guided by a complex ‘program’ for its development. Notice that as each part comes to be it already has the functional capacity associated with it—it comes to be and is ensouled .

As for hardness, softness, toughness and fragility and all the other such affections present in these ensouled parts, these affections might be produced by heat and cold, but not the defining character ( logos ) in virtue of which the one part is flesh and the other bone; that is the result of the movement derived from the generator, being in actuality what that out of which it comes to be is potentially, just as in things that come to be by craftsmanship. (734b31–35)

This passage comes immediately after Aristotle has stressed two related points: that the uniform parts and the instrumental parts arise simultaneously; and that even flesh and bone have a function to perform. These points are tightly connected. The defining features of tissues are not merely their affective qualities such as being hard or soft, but their biological functions as well; and their biological functions are intimately connected to their roles in constituting— and being able to play functional roles in —instrumental parts; many, if not all, of a part’s affective qualities are a consequence of its biological role.

In the process of making this argument, Aristotle also stresses a crucial and problematic dis -analogy: Natural things, once their generation begins, ‘grow by means of themselves’ (735a13–14). This is the most fundamental difference between art and nature for Aristotle; a nature is a source of change within the thing itself ( Physics II. 1). Natural development, then, though initiated by the warmth contributed by the male parent, continues by means of a source of change within the developing embryo. The carpenter may not mix any of his own material in his buildings; but he must be continuously, physically involved in the movements that create those buildings. Not so with the male parent in natural generation. So how does a complex process that has its origins in an external generator become a natural process of development?

For Aristotle, the heart (or its analogue in bloodless animals) is crucial. It is the first part created by the heat derived from the semen of the male parent, and henceforth it is the primary internal source of that heat and thus of further development (735a16–26). The following explanation begins to bring us into contact with our passage on generation from the History of Animals .

…in the embryo ( kuema ), while in a way all the parts are present potentially, the source [of development] is most along the path to actuality. This is why the heart is first to be differentiated in actuality. And this is not only clear to perception (as it happens), but is also clear to reason. When the developing thing is distinct from both the male and female contributions, it must manage itself, as when a son sets up a home away from his father. So in animals there must be a source of generation from which the later organizing of the body comes about. … Wherefore the heart appears differentiated first in all blooded animals; for it is the source of both the uniform and the non-uniform parts. … And the prepared blood or its analogue is nutrient for the animal, and the blood vessels are its repository; for this reason the heart is their source. This is clear from a study of ‘the histories’ and ‘the dissections’. (740a2–23, excerpted; compare 735a12–26, 738b17–18 740a27–36, 742b34–743a1, 743b26)

Having developed this general explanation during his discussion of his central case, viviparous development, in GA II, Aristotle moves on to egg-laying animals in book III. GA III 1 carries over to them whatever is common to the two cases, with discussion of the development of birds in their eggs beginning in GA III 2. A recurring aspect of his argument, here as in PA , is to refer us for descriptive details to the histories (presumably the basis of our HA ) and to a collection of representations of dissections (tragically not preserved, but cited repeatedly in Aristotle’s biological writings and in ancient catalogues of his writings).

The most general differences among egg-layers relate to the ‘completeness’ of the egg when laid. Because birds lay eggs that become hard as soon as they are exposed to the air (752a30-b2), they are taken to be better prepared when laid than the eggs of other egg-laying animals. Ignoring much interesting and important detail, we will take up the discussion of development within the eggs of birds as they incubate. Aristotle distinguishes the ‘white’ and the ‘yolk’, not descriptively as he did in HA , but functionally (752b18–28).

…it is the white out of which the animal is constituted, while the yolk becomes nutrient, and growth for the constitution of the parts is from it. This is also why the yolk and the white, having distinct natures, have been kept distinct by membranes. For precise details concerning how these parts are situated in relation to each other in virtue of the sources of generation and the constitution of animals, as well as the membranes and umbilical cords, one should study what has been outlined in the histories. The following appears to be sufficient for the present investigation: the heart is the first thing constituted; after this the great blood vessel is marked off, and two umbilical cords extend from this blood vessel, one to the membrane around the yolk, the other to the membrane surrounding the animal itself. This latter is thus next to the membrane of the shell. (753b11–23)

In this case (though not always) one does get far more detail in HA . These references to histories and dissections can be misleading unless one takes into account the differences in the aims, and thus in the organization, of these treatises. In this case, for example, nothing is said in GA about the heart ‘beating and moving as though it were alive’. As we saw, however, GA II stresses that in the development of live-bearing animals, the heart is first to be formed, is ensouled from the start, and is the source of development for all the other parts—a much more ‘theory-laden’ characterization that stresses the heart’s causal role in development. And because of the organizational structure of GA , much of what is said in his discussion of the live-bearing animals (those that are ‘more complete’ when they are born) is assumed to apply to animals that lay eggs (that are ‘less complete’ when born).

Recall the stunningly accurate discussion of the head and eyes of the four day old chick embryo in HA (in section 5.1, above). This is not discussed in GA III 2; however in GA II 6, in a long discussion of early organ formation in live-bearing animals, Aristotle has a good deal to say on the subject:

What happens concerning the eyes of animals presents a problem. For from the beginning, whether in land animals, swimmers or flyers, they appear very large and yet they are among the last of the parts to be completed and in the mean time contract in size. This is because the sense organs of the eyes are, as with the other sense organs, on channels; but while those for touch and taste are simply bodily, or some part of the body of animals, and those for smell and hearing are channels connected to the air outside and are full of connate pneuma…the eyes alone have a proper sensory body. (743b33–744a6)

The full explanation goes on much longer, but we need not follow it out for the purposes of making two important points about the relationship of GA to HA . The first is that the organization of GA dictates that for the explanation of facts of wide generality such as this one, we must look in book II—notice that he claims that this explanation for the large size of eyes early in development and for their subsequent contraction applies to all land, air and water animals. The second point to be stressed is the relentlessly causal/explanatory focus of the GA discussion, a feature (properly) completely absent in the corresponding discussions in HA . As impressive as the descriptive accuracy of the embryological passage cited earlier from HA is, we again need to remember what is absent from that discussion. For the equally impressive embryological theory , the reader of Aristotle’s biology must turn to the Generation of Animals .

This entry on Aristotle’s biology and its philosophy closes with a puzzle about the organization of his biological works when compared with the remainder of the Aristotelian corpus. I began by noting that it is a fundamental aspect of Aristotle’s theory of science that investigation proceeds from a stage where one establishes the existence of the things being studied and the facts about them to a stage where the focus is on causal explanations by reference to the natures and essences of those things. It seems clear that the biological works honor this distinction, and do so self-consciously. Yet Aristotle never suggests, in the Posterior Analytics or anywhere else, that these stages should be represented by distinct treatises devoted to the same subject. Indeed, in no other domain does Aristotle do this: whether we look to meteorology, cosmology, psychology, ethics, drama or rhetoric, we find single treatises presenting both the facts and their explanation. Nor can this puzzle be easily dismissed as an artifact of later editing—as I have pointed out a number of times, these treatises have a most interesting and consistent pattern of cross-referencing. The treatises that report the results of causal investigations regularly refer to HA (and the dissections) for more detail regarding the facts being explained; the HA , in contrast, never refers to the causal treatises. Moreover, the striking avoidance in the Historia Animalium of all of the concepts associated with definition and explanation cannot reasonably be laid at the feet of some imagined later editor. We are left, then, to ponder what it was about the investigation of animals that led Aristotle to take a methodological distinction regarding stages of investigation and reify it in methodologically distinct treatises devoted to these different stages.

  • Balme, D. M., 1991, Aristotle. History of Animals, Books VII–X , Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1992, Aristotle. De Partibus Animalium I and De Generatione Animalium I (with passages from II. 1–3) With a Report on Recent Work and an Additional Bibliography by A. Gotthelf , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2002, Aristotle: Historia Animalium, Volume I , Books I-X Text (prepared for publication by A. Gotthelf), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Carbone, A., 2002, Aristotele: Le Parti degli Animali , Milano: Biblioteca Universale Rizzoli.
  • Drossaart Lulofs, H. J., 1965, Aristotelis De Generatione Animalium , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Düring, I., 1943/1980 repr., Aristotle’s De Partibus Animalium : Critical and Literary Commentaries , New York: Garland Publishing.
  • Epstein, K., 2019, Aristoteles: Historia Animalium Buch VIII und IX , Berlin: De Gruyter.
  • Kullmann, W., 2007, Aristoteles: Über die Teile der Lebewesen , Berlin: Akademie Verlag.
  • Lanza, D., Vegetti, M., 1971, Aristotele, Opere Biologiche , Torino: UTET.
  • Le Blond, J. M., 1945, Aristote, philosophe de la vie: Le livre premier du traité sur les Parties des Animaux. Paris: Aubier.
  • Lennox, J. G., 2001a, Aristotle: On the Parts of Animals , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Louis, P., 1956, Les parties des animaux , Paris: Budé.
  • –––, 1961, De la génération des animaux , Paris: Budé.
  • Ogle, W., 1882/1987, Aristotle on the Parts of Animals. New York: Garland.
  • Peck. A. L., 1961, Aristotle: Parts of Animals (introduction, text, translation), Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1963, Aristotle: Generation of Animals (introduction, text, translation), Loeb Classical Library. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1965, Aristotle: Historia Animalium, Books I-III (introduction, text, translation), Loeb Classical Library, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • –––, 1970, Aristotle: Historia Animalium, Books IV-VI (introduction, text, translation), Loeb Classical Library, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
  • Pellegrin, P., 2011, Aristote: Les Parties des Animaux , Paris: GF Flammarion.
  • –––, 2017, Aristote: Histoire des Animaux , Paris: GF Flammarion.
  • Primavesi, O. and K. Corcilius eds., 2018, Aristoteles De motu animalium: Über die Bewegung der Lebenwesen (Greek Text and German Translation), Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.
  • Rapp, C. and O. Primavesi eds., 2020, Aristotle’s De Motu Animalium (Symposium Aristotelicum, with Greek Text and English Translation), Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Ross, W. D., 1949, Aristotle’s Prior and Posterior Analytics: A Revised Text with Introduction and Commentary , Oxford: The Clarendon Press.
  • Schneiders, S., 2019, Aristoteles: Historia Animalium Buch VIII und IX , Berlin: De Gruyter.
  • Whitteridge, G., 1981, William Harvey: Disputations touching The Generation of Animals , Oxford: Blackwell Scientific Publications.
  • Anagnostopoulos, G. (ed.), 2009, A Companion to Aristotle , Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell.
  • Balme, D. M., 1961, “Aristotle’s Use of Differentiae in Zoology,” in S. Mansion (ed.), Aristote e les problèmes de méthode , Louvain: Publications Universitaires de Louvain, pp. 195–212.
  • –––, 1987a, “The Place of Biology in Aristotle’s Philosophy,” in Gotthelf & Lennox 1987, pp. 9–20.
  • –––, 1987b, “Aristotle’s Use of Division and Differentiae,” in Gotthelf & Lennox 1987, pp. 69–89.
  • –––, 1987c, “Aristotle’s biology was not essentialist,” in Gotthelf & Lennox 1987, pp. 291–312.
  • –––, 1990, “Matter in definition: a reply to G. E. R. Lloyd,” in Devereux & Pellegrin 1990, pp. 49–54.
  • Bartos, H. and C. G. King (eds.), 2020, Heat, Pneuma, and Soul in Ancient Philosophy and Science , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Bolton, R., 1987, “Definition and Scientific Method in Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics and Generation of Animals ,” in Gotthelf & Lennox 1987, pp. 120–66.
  • –––, 2010, “Biology and metaphysics in Aristotle”, in Lennox and Bolton, pp. 30–55.
  • Bowen, A. (ed.), 1991, Science and Philosophy in Classical Greece , New York: Garland Press.
  • Bronstein, D., 2016, Aristotle on Knowledge and Learning: The Posterior Analytics , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Charles, D., 1988, “Aristotle on Hypothetical Necessity and Irreducibility,” Pacific Philosophical Quarterly , 69: 1–45.
  • –––, 1990, “Meaning, natural kinds and natural history,” in Devereux & Pellegrin 1990, pp. 145–67.
  • –––, 2000, Aristotle on Meaning and Essence , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • ––– (ed.), 2010, Definition in Greek Philosophy , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • –––, 2012, “Teleological Causation,” in Shields 2012, pp. 226–266.
  • Code, A., 1986, “Soul as Efficient Cause in Aristotle’s Embryology,” Philosophical Topics , 15: 51–60.
  • –––, 1997, “The Priority of Final Causes over Efficient Causes in Aristotle’s Parts of Animals ,” in Kullmann und Föllinger 1997, pp. 127–144.
  • Connell, S. M., 2016, Aristotle on Female Animals: A Study of the Generation of Animals, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • ––– (ed.), 2021, The Cambridge Companion to Aristotle’s Biology , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Cooper, J. M., 1988, “Metaphysics in Aristotle’s Embryology,” Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society , 214: 14–41.
  • Depew, D., 2008, “Consequence Etiology and Biological Teleology in Aristotle and Darwin,” Studies in the History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences , 39: 379–390.
  • Detel, W., 1999, “Aristotle on Zoological Explanation,” Philosophical Topics , 25: 43–68.
  • Devereux, D. & Pellegrin, P. (eds.), 1990, Biologie, Logique et Métaphysique chez Aristote , Paris: Éditions du CNRS.
  • Ebrey, D., 2015, Theory and Practice in Aristotle’s Natural Science , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Falcon, A. and D. Lefebvre eds., 2018, Aristotle’s Generation of Animals: A Critical Guide , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Föllinger. S. (ed.), 2010, Was ist ‘Leben’? Aristoteles’ Anschauungen zur Entstehung und Funktionsweise von Leben , Stuttgart: Franz Steiner Verlag.
  • –––, 2010, “Das Problem des Leben in Aristoteles’ Embryologie,” in Föllinger 2010, pp. 225–236.
  • Fortenbaugh, W. W., & Sharples, R. W. (eds.), 1988, Theophrastean Studies , New Brunswick: Rutgers University Press.
  • Furth, M., 1988, Substance, Form and Psyche: An Aristotelean Metaphysics , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Gelber, J., 2010, “Form and Inheritance in Aristotle’s Embryology,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy XXXIX (Winter): 183–212.
  • –––, 2015, “Are Facts about Matter Primitive?,” in Ebrey 2015, pp. 46–60.
  • –––, 2015, “Aristotle on Essence and Habitat,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy , 48: 267–293.
  • –––, 2018, “Two Ways of Being for an End”, Phronesis , 63: 64–86.
  • Gill, M. L., 1989, “Aristotle on Matters of Life and Death,” Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy , 4: 187–205.
  • –––, 1997, “Material Necessity and Meteorology IV 12,” in Kullmann and Föllinger 1997, pp. 145–162.
  • Gotthelf, A. (ed.), 1985a, Aristotle on Nature and Living Things: philosophical and historical studies presented to David M. Balme on his seventieth birthday , Pittsburgh: Mathesis.
  • –––, 1985b, “Notes towards a study of substance and essence in Aristotle’s Parts of Animals II-IV,” in Gotthelf 1985a, pp. 27–54.
  • –––, 1987a, “First principles in Aristotle’s Parts of Animals ,” in Gotthelf & Lennox 1987, pp. 167–98.
  • –––, 1987b, “Aristotle’s Conception of Final Causality,” in Gotthelf & Lennox 1987, pp. 204–242.
  • –––, 1988, “Historiae I: Plantarum e Animalium,” in Fortenbaugh & Sharples 1988, pp. 100–135.
  • –––, 1997a, “The elephant’s nose: further reflections on the axiomatic structure of biological explanation in Aristotle,” in Kullmann & Föllinger 1997, pp. 85–96.
  • –––, 1997b, “Division and Explanation in Aristotle’s Parts of Animals ,” in Günther & Rengakos 1997, pp. 215–230.
  • –––, 2012, Teleology, First Principles, and Scientific Method in Aristotle’s Biology , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Gotthelf, A. & Lennox, J. G. (eds.), 1987, Philosophical Issues in Aristotle’s Biology , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Günther, H.-C. & Rengakos, A. (eds.) 1997, Beiträge zur antiken Philosophie: Festschrift für Wolfgang Kullmann , Stuttgart: Franz Steiner.
  • Henry, D., 2003, “Themistius and Spontaneous Generation in Aristotle’s Metaphysics ,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy , 24: 183–208.
  • –––, 2006a, “Understanding Aristotle’s Reproductive Hylomorphism,” Apeiron , 39: 269–300.
  • –––, 2006b, “Aristotle on the Mechanisms of Inheritance,” Journal of the History of Biology , 39: 425–455.
  • –––, 2008, “Organismal Natures,” Apeiron: A Journal for Ancient philosophy and science , 41: 47–74.
  • –––, 2011, “Aristotle’s Pluralistic Realism,” The Monist , 94(2): 198–222.
  • –––, 2013,“Optimality and Teleology in Aristotle’s Natural Science,” Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy , XLV (Winter): 225–263.
  • –––, 2019, Aristotle on Matter, Form, and Moving Causes: The Hylomorphic Theory of Substantial Generation , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2021, “Essence and Definition in Aristotle’s Parts of Animals ,” British Journal for the History of Philosophy , first online 02 Mar 2021 doi:10.1080/09608788.2021.1881442
  • Johnson, M., 2005, Aristotle on Teleology , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Keil, G. and N. Kreft (eds.), 2019, Aristotle’s Anthropology , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Korobili, G. and R. Lo Presti (eds.), 2021, Nutrition and Nutritive Soul in Aristotle and Aristotelianism , Berlin: De Gruyter.
  • Kullmann, W., 1974, Wissenschaft und Methode , Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
  • Kullmann, W. and Föllinger, S. (eds.), 1997, Aristotelische Biologie , Stuttgart: Franz Steiner.
  • Labbarrière, J-L., 2004, Language, vie politiques et mouvement des animaux: Études aristotéliciennes , Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin.
  • Lennox, J., 1990, “Notes on David Charles on HA ,” in Devereux & Pellegrin 1990, pp. 169–183.
  • –––, 2001b, Aristotle’s Philosophy of Biology: Studies in the Origins of Life Science , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2001c, “Aristotle on the Unity and Disunity of Science,” International Studies in Philosophy of Science , 15 (2): 133–144.
  • –––, 2005, “Getting a Science Going: Aristotle on Entry Level Kinds,” in Wolters & Carrier 2005, pp. 87–100.
  • –––, 2009, “Form, Essence, and Explanation in Aristotle’s Biology,” in Anagnostopoulos 2009, pp. 348–367.
  • –––, 2010a, “Bios and Explanatory Unity in Aristotle’s Biology,” in Charles 2010, pp. 329–355.
  • –––, 2010b, “The unity and purpose of On the Parts of Animals I,” in Lennox and Bolton 2010, pp. 56–77.
  • –––, 2011, “Aristotle on Norms of Inquiry,” HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science , 1: 23–46.
  • –––, 2012, “The Complexity of Aristotle’s Study of Animals,” in Shields 2012, pp. 287–305.
  • –––, 2017, “An Aristotelian Philosophy of Biology: Form, Function, and Development”, Acta Philosophica , I: 33–51.
  • –––, 2018, “Aristotle on the Origins of Zoology”, in Cambridge History of Science, Vol. 1 , A. Jones and L. Taub (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 215–237.
  • –––, 2020, “Aristotle on the Unity of the Nutritive and Reproductive Functions”, Phronesis , 65(4): 414–466. (Co–authored with Cameron Coates)
  • –––, 2021, “Biology and Cosmology in Aristotle”, in Cosmology and Biology in Ancient Philosophy: From Thales to Avicenna , R. Salles (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 109–130.
  • –––, 2021, Aristotle on Inquiry: Erotetic Frameworks and Domain Specific Norms , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Lennox, J. and Bolton, R. (eds.), 2010, Being, Nature, and Life in Aristotle , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Leroi, A. M., 2014, The Lagoon: How Aristotle Invented Science , London: Bloomsbury Circus.
  • Lesher, J. (ed.), 2010, From Inquiry to Demonstrative Knowledge: New Essays on Aristotle’s Posterior Analytics, Kelowna BC: Academic Printing and Publishing.
  • Leunissen, M., 2010a, Explanation and Teleology in Aristotle’s Science of Nature , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • –––, 2010b, “Aristotle’s Syllogistic Model of Knowledge and the Biological Sciences: Demonstrating Natural Processes,” in Lesher 2010, pp. 31–60.
  • –––, 2010c, “Nature as a good House-keeper: Secondary Teleology and Material Necessity in Aristotle’s Biology”, Apeiron , 43(4): 117–142.
  • –––, 2017, From Natural Character to Moral Virtue in Aristotle , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Leunissen, M. and Gotthelf, A., 2010, “What’s Teleology Got to Do with It: A Reinterpretation of Aristotle’s Generation of Animals V,” Phronesis , 55: 325–356.
  • Lloyd, G. E. R., 1987, “Empirical research in Aristotle’s biology,” in Gotthelf & Lennox 1987, pp. 53–64.
  • –––, 1990, “Aristotle’s zoology and his metaphysics. The status quaestionis . A critical review of some recent theories,” in Devereux & Pellegrin 1990, pp. 7–36.
  • –––, 1996, Aristotelian Explorations , Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Marcos, A., 1996, Aristóteles y Otros Animales , Barcelona: Promociones y Publicaciones Universitarias.
  • Mayhew, R., 2004, The Female in Aristotle’s Biology , Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Mingucci, G. 2015, La fisiologia del pensiero in Aristotele , Bologna: Il Mulino.
  • Morel, P-M., 2007, De la matiére á l’action aristote et le problème du vivant , Paris: Librairie Philosophique J. Vrin.
  • Owen, R., 1992, The Hunterian Lectures in Comparative Anatomy (May and June 1837) , Phillip Reid Sloan (ed.), Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Pellegrin, P., 1986, Aristotle’s Classification of Animals: Biology and the Conceptual Unity of the Aristotelian Corpus , trans. by Anthony Preus, Berkeley: University of California Press.
  • Quarantotto, D., 2005, Causa Finale, Sostanza, Essenza in Aristotele , Napoli: Bibliopolis.
  • Shields, C., 2012, The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle , Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Stavrianeas, S., 2009, “Spontaneous Generation in Aristotle’s Biology,” Rhizai: A Journal of Ancient Philosophy and Science , 5: 303–338.
  • Tipton, J.A., 2014, Philosophical Biology in Aristotle’s Parts of Animals , Heidelberg: Springer.
  • Wolters, G. & Carrier, M. (eds.), 2005, Homo Sapiens und Homo Faber: epistemische und technische Rationalität in Antike und Gegenwart , Festschrift für Jürgen Mittelstrass, Berlin: De Gruyter.
How to cite this entry . Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society . Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO). Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers , with links to its database.

[Please contact the author with suggestions.]

Aristotle | Aristotle, General Topics: logic | Aristotle, General Topics: metaphysics | Aristotle, Special Topics: causality | soul, ancient theories of

Copyright © 2021 by James Lennox

  • Accessibility

Support SEP

Mirror sites.

View this site from another server:

  • Info about mirror sites

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2023 by The Metaphysics Research Lab , Department of Philosophy, Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

Earlham sophomore to present research paper at World Congress of Philosophy in Rome

research paper on aristotle

RICHMOND, Ind. — Plato, a famous philosopher who lived in ancient Greece, once said " There will be no end to the troubles of states, or of humanity itself, till philosophers become kings in this world."

The mere concept of "world" will now be presented at the 25th World Congress of Philosophy in Rome, Italy Aug. 4 by an Earlham College student.

Sophomore Jimmy Freiberger will present his research paper titled "Exposition of World and Comportment Toward World in Heidegger" to philosophers from all around the world. This will be Freiberger's first presentation to an outside conference, according to an Earlham College press release.

Freiberger's paper was originally an assignment for his philosophy class taught by Professor Ferit Güven. Freiberger said in a news release he was inspired to write the paper through his own advocacy.

“As someone who is interested in helping create a better world, I want to understand what the world is first,” he said in the release. “I feel like, too often, in advocacy we might jump headfirst into something in the pursuit of changing the world, without first questioning if we have the ability to change the world or if the world is something that would allow itself to be changed.”

This year's theme for the conference, typically held every five years, is "Philosophy across Boundaries" and will be held from Aug. 1 to Aug. 8. The aim of the conference is to "foster scholarly and public reflections on the future of our societies," according to its website.

“This will include philosophers from all over the world and I’ll be reading in front of a large crowd, but even if I receive harsh criticism, that’s good, right?” Freiberger said. “There are very few other opportunities to receive that degree of feedback.”

Freiberger was also awarded the Endeavor Fellowship which allows him to participate in the 2024 Athens Democracy Forum from Oct. 1 to Oct. 4. The theme of the forum is “A Moment of Truth,” and attendees will be urged to question topics related to climate technology, journalism and the very state of democracy.

Part of why Freiberger enjoys philosophy is the ability to invoke communication and question life itself.

“Through philosophy, we can call into question our participation in the structures and institutions of daily life, and recognize their absurdities,” he said in the release. “We’re developing and forming our ideas through dialogue with our professors and peers. I think that’s very valuable.”

Upon receiving his degree from Earlham, Freiberger plans to enter a dual program to earn a Ph.D. in philosophy and a J.D. in law, which he hopes to use to become a civil rights attorney and eventually president of the United States.

Evan Weaver is a news and sports reporter at The Palladium-Item. Contact him on X (@evan_weaver7) or email at [email protected].

IMAGES

  1. SOLUTION: Aristotle Biography Paper

    research paper on aristotle

  2. Reaction Paper To Aristotle's Life and Education

    research paper on aristotle

  3. Aristotle Philosophical Perspective

    research paper on aristotle

  4. (PDF) ARISTOTLE, PLATO, AND SOCRATES: ANCIENT GREEK PERSPECTIVES ON

    research paper on aristotle

  5. (PDF) Essay on Aristotle's Function Argument

    research paper on aristotle

  6. Aristotle Philosophical Perspective

    research paper on aristotle

VIDEO

  1. BA III YEAR 1st paper ARISTOTLE: scientific method by: Dr.SHRADHA TIWARI

  2. Aristotle's Concept of Slavery

  3. Aristotle⎥Conception of the World & of Man

  4. Basic Introduction about Aristotle

  5. biography of aristotle

  6. Aristotle's Classification of State/Government|URDU/HINDI| CSS|PMS|

COMMENTS

  1. Aristotle (384-322 bc): philosopher and scientist of ancient Greece

    Aristotle was one of the greatest philosophers and scientists the world has ever seen. He was born in 384 bc at Stagirus, a Greek seaport on the coast of Thrace. His father, Nichomachus, court physician to King Amyntus II of Macedon, died while he was still a boy, and his guardian, Proxenus, sent him to complete his education at the age of 17 in Plato's Academy in Athens.

  2. (PDF) Aristotle's Poetics

    Abstract. This paper provides an overview and commentary of Aristotle's theory of poetry, of drama, and of narrative structure, as presented the Poetics. The main emphasis falls on plot structure ...

  3. (PDF) The Virtue of Aristotle's Ethics

    The Virtue of Aristotle's Ethics. by. Paula Gottlieb, Full Professor of Philosophy. and Affiliate Professor of Classics, University of Wisconsin-Madison. August 2008. PDF | While Aristotle's ...

  4. Aristotle

    The aim of the congress was to advance scholarship on all aspects of Aristotle's work, both in philosophy and in the fundamental disciplines of science. The impressive number of 250 papers from 40 countries highlighted the fact that Aristotle's work continues to exercise an influence on our intellectual lives on a global scale.

  5. Aristotle's Political Theory

    Aristotle (b. 384-d. 322 BCE), was a Greek philosopher, logician, and scientist. Along with his teacher Plato, Aristotle is generally regarded as one of the most influential ancient thinkers in a number of philosophical fields, including political theory. Aristotle was born in Stagira in northern Greece, and his father was a court physician ...

  6. The Oxford Handbook of Aristotle

    The book, prefaced with an introduction to Aristotle's life and works by the editor, covers the main areas of Aristotelian philosophy and intellectual enquiry: ethics, metaphysics, politics, logic, language, psychology, rhetoric, poetics, theology, physical and biological investigation, and philosophical method. ...

  7. Aristotle's 'Rhetoric' as a Work of Philosophy

    Aristotle's Rhetoric stands out as an anomaly in his corpus; his other works - except for other anomalies like the Constitution of Athens - are explorations of philosophie and scientific problems, while the Rhetoric looks like a handbook teaching speakers how to be persuasive. It's not surprising, then, that people in departments of English and ...

  8. Aristotle, the Action Researcher

    The Ways of Aristotle: Aristotelian Phronesis, Aristotelian Philosophy of Dialogue, and Action Research. Olav Eikeland. Bern, Peter Lang, 2008. Pp. 560.Pbk. £54.00. This article discusses Olav Eikeland's The Ways of Aristotle, a book that takes stock of a whole range of Aristotelian themes and communicates various complex Aristotelian ideas ...

  9. Aristotle's Art of Rhetoric: Translated and with an Interpretive Essay

    Aristotle traces lexis's beginnings to actors' recitations of poetry, which, as Plato's Ion reminds us, may have little or nothing to do with anything the speaker understands. Aristotle here addresses the more "vulgar" aspects of rhetoric, including grammar, clarity, rhythm, metaphor, tone, and volume, to name a few.

  10. [PDF] Aristotle's Virtue Ethics

    Aristotle, though not the first Greek virtue ethicist, was the first to establish virtue ethics as a distinct philosophical discipline. His exposition of the subject in his Nicomachean Ethics set the terms of subsequent debate in the European and Arabic traditions by proposing a set of plausible assumptions from which virtue ethics should proceed. His conception of human well-being and virtue ...

  11. Aristotle's Rhetoric

    The methodical core of Aristotle's Rhetoric is the theorem that there are three 'technical' pisteis , i.e. 'persuaders' or 'means of persuasion'. Persuasion comes about either through the character ( êthos) of the speaker, the emotional state ( pathos) of the hearer, or the argument ( logos ) itself.

  12. Aristotle's Psychology

    Aristotle's Psychology. First published Tue Jan 11, 2000; substantive revision Mon Oct 12, 2020. Aristotle (384-322 BC) was born in Macedon, in what is now northern Greece, but spent most of his adult life in Athens. His life in Athens divides into two periods, first as a member of Plato's Academy (367-347) and later as director of his ...

  13. Aristotle

    Aristotle was born on the Chalcidic peninsula of Macedonia, in northern Greece. His father, Nicomachus, was the physician of Amyntas III (reigned c. 393-c. 370 bce ), king of Macedonia and grandfather of Alexander the Great (reigned 336-323 bce ). After his father's death in 367, Aristotle migrated to Athens, where he joined the Academy ...

  14. PhilPapers: Online Research in Philosophy

    PhilPapers is a comprehensive index and bibliography of philosophy maintained by the community of philosophers. We monitor all sources of research content in philosophy, including journals, books, and open access archives . We also host the largest open access archive in philosophy . Our index currently contains 2,861,781 entries categorized in ...

  15. Understanding Aristotle

    Philosophy papers on Aristotle are found under "Ancient" (Ancient Greek Philosophy). Paideia Project On-Line. The Paideia Project On-Line contains philosophy papers in its archives, including papers on Aristotle. You can look for Aristotle under "Ancient Philosophy" heading or type Aristotle's name in the search box. Not all of the papers are ...

  16. [PDF] Aristotle's logic.

    The place of logic in Aristotle's thought In Metaph. E.1, Aristotle divides the sciences (=branches of knowledge) into three divisions: Theoretical (mathematics, natural science, theology), Practical (ethics, politics), and Productive (art, rhetoric). They are distinguished by their aims—truth, action, and production, respectively. Where is logic on this list? Aristotle does not seem to ...

  17. Aristotle Research Paper Topics

    Aristotle's politics provides a fertile ground for research on topics such as his views on the best form of government, the role of the middle class, and the relationship between ethics and politics. In the realm of rhetoric and poetics, Aristotle research paper topics could explore his concepts of ethos, pathos, and logos, his theory of ...

  18. The role of education in Aristotle's Politics

    Abstract. Aristotle analyzed the problem of education in the seventh and eighth books of Politics. Most researchers interpret his thoughts on education as "the education of the youth". Some ...

  19. Aristotle's Biology

    Aristotle's Biology. First published Wed Feb 15, 2006; substantive revision Fri Jul 16, 2021. Aristotle is properly recognized as the originator of the scientific study of life. This is true despite the fact that many earlier Greek natural philosophers occasionally speculated on the origins of living things and much of the Hippocratic medical ...

  20. PDF Research Paper on Aristotle Poetics and Criticism

    Keywords: Aristotle's ideals, poetics, criticism, Aristotelian Tragedy. 1. PREFACE Considered to be one of the most influential literary figures not only in Greece but also in all over the world; This figure is the great Greek philosopher Aristotle. Aristotle‟s passion to reach ideal forms of any social or literary structure was the

  21. Aristotle's virtue ethics as a conceptual framework for the study and

    This paper aims to highlight the importance of Aristotle's model of virtue ethics for today's social workers and students, as it can help them to build an ethical character and promote ethical ...

  22. Aristotle

    Aristotle - Politics, Philosophy, Logic: Turning from the Ethics treatises to their sequel, the Politics, the reader is brought down to earth. "Man is a political animal," Aristotle observes; human beings are creatures of flesh and blood, rubbing shoulders with each other in cities and communities. Like his work in zoology, Aristotle's political studies combine observation and theory.

  23. Earlham College sophomore to present research paper in Rome

    Earlham sophomore to present research paper at World Congress of Philosophy in Rome. RICHMOND, Ind. — Plato, a famous philosopher who lived in ancient Greece, once said " There will be no end to ...

  24. (PDF) political philosophy research paper Aristotle

    Abstract. this paper discusses the ideas and thoughts of prominent Greek Philosopher Aristotele and why he was so interested in such ideas those include Education, logic, roots of Anarchy Justice ...